LIBRARY OF THE FUTURE (R) First Edition Ver. 4.02 
 Critique of Judgement                                            Kant Immanuel         

                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                      1790                                  
                                                                            
                           THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT                        
                                                                            
                                by Immanuel Kant                            
                                                                            
                       translated by James Creed Meredith                   
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
                                                                            
 Electronically Enhanced Text (c) Copyright 1991, World Library, Inc.       
                                                                            
PREFACE                                                                     
            PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION 1790.                              
-                                                                           
  The faculty of knowledge from a priori principles may be called pure      
reason, and the general investigation into its possibility and              
bounds the Critique of Pure Reason. This is permissible although "pure      
reason," as was the case with the same use of terms in our first work,      
is only intended to denote reason in its theoretical employment, and        
although there is no desire to bring under review its faculty as            
practical reason and its special principles as such. That Critique is,      
then, an investigation addressed simply to our faculty of knowing           
things a priori. Hence it makes our cognitive faculties its sole            
concern, to the exclusion of the feeling of pleasure or displeasure         
and the faculty of desire; and among the cognitive faculties it             
confines its attention to understanding and its a priori principles,        
to the exclusion of judgement and reason, (faculties that also              
belong to theoretical cognition,) because it turns out in the sequel        
that there is no cognitive faculty other than understanding capable of      
affording constitutive a priori principles of knowledge. Accordingly        
the critique which sifts these faculties one and all, so as to try the      
possible claims of each of the other faculties to a share in the clear      
possession of knowledge from roots of its own, retains nothing but          
what understanding prescribes a priori as a law for nature as the           
complex of phenomena-the form of these being similarly furnished a          
priori. All other pure concepts it relegates to the rank of ideas,*         
which for our faculty of theoretical cognition are transcendent;            
though they are not without their use nor redundant, but discharge          
certain functions as regulative principles.** For these concepts serve      
partly to restrain the officious pretentions of understanding,              
which, presuming on its ability to supply a priori the conditions of        
the possibility of all things which it is capable of knowing,               
behaves as if it had thus determined these bounds as those of the           
possibility of all things generally, and partly also to lead                
understanding, in its study of nature, according to a principle of          
completeness, unattainable as this remains for it, and so to promote        
the ultimate aim of all knowledge.                                          
-                                                                           
  *[The word is defined in SS 17 & SS 57 Remark I. See Critique of          
Pure Reason, "Of the Conceptions of Pure Reason" - Section 1 & 2:           
"I understand by idea a necessary conception of reason, to which no         
corresponding object can be discovered in the world of sense."              
(Ibid., Section 2.) "They contain a certain perfection, attainable          
by no possible empirical cognition; and they give to reason a               
systematic unity, to which the unity of experience attempts to              
approximate, but can never completely attain." (Ibid., "Ideal of            
Pure Reason").                                                              
  **[Cf. Critique of Pure Reason, Appendix.]                                
-                                                                           
                                                      {PREFACE ^paragraph 5}
  Properly, therefore, it was understanding which, so far as it             
contains constitutive a priori cognitive principles, has its special        
realm, and one, moreover, in our faculty of knowledge that the              
Critique, called in a general way that of pure reason was intended          
to establish in secure but particular possession against all other          
competitors. In the same way reason, which contains constitutive a          
priori principles solely in respect of the faculty of desire, gets its      
holding assigned to it by The Critique of Practical Reason.                 
  But now comes judgement, which in the order of our cognitive              
faculties forms a middle term between understanding and reason. Has it      
also got independent a priori principles? If so, are they                   
constitutive, or are they merely regulative, thus indicating no             
special realm? And do they give a rule a priori to the feeling of           
pleasure and displeasure, as the middle term between the faculties          
of cognition and desire, just as understanding prescribes laws a            
priori for the former and reason for the latter? This is the topic          
to which the present Critique is devoted.                                   
  A critique of pure reason, i.e., of our faculty of judging on a           
priori principles, would be incomplete if the critical examination          
of judgement, which is a faculty of knowledge, and as such lays             
claim to independent principles, were not dealt with separately.            
Still, however, its principles cannot, in a system of pure philosophy,      
form a separate constituent part intermediate between the                   
theoretical and practical divisions, but may when needful be annexed        
to one or other as occasion requires. For if such a system is some day      
worked out under the general name of metaphysic-and its full and            
complete execution is both possible and of the utmost importance for        
the employment of reason in all departments of its activity-the             
critical examination of the ground for this edifice must have been          
previously carried down to the very depths of the foundations of the        
faculty of principles independent of experience, lest in some               
quarter it might give way, and sinking, inevitably bring with it the        
ruin of all.                                                                
  We may readily gather, however, from the nature of the faculty of         
judgement (whose correct employment is so necessary and universally         
requisite that it is just this faculty that is intended when we             
speak of sound understanding) that the discovery of a peculiar              
principle belonging to it-and some such it must contain in itself a         
priori, for otherwise it would not be a cognitive faculty the               
distinctive character of which is obvious to the most commonplace           
criticism-must be a task involving considerable difficulties. For this      
principle is one which must not be derived from a priori concepts,          
seeing that these are the property of understanding, and judgement          
is only directed to their application. It has, therefore, itself to         
furnish a concept, and one from which, properly, we get no cognition        
of a thing, but which it can itself employ as a rule only-but not as        
an objective rule to which it can adapt its judgement, because, for         
that, another faculty of judgement would again be required to enable        
us to decide whether the case was one for the application of the            
rule or not.                                                                
  It is chiefly in those estimates that are called aesthetic, and           
which relate to the beautiful and sublime, whether of nature or of          
art, that one meets with the above difficulty about a principle (be it      
subjective or objective). And yet the critical search for a                 
principle of judgement in their case is the most important item in a        
critique of this faculty. For, although they do not of themselves           
contribute a whit to the knowledge of things, they still belong wholly      
to the faculty of knowledge, and evidence an immediate bearing of this      
faculty upon the feeling of pleasure or displeasure according to            
some a priori principle, and do so without confusing this principle         
with what is capable of being a determining ground of the faculty of        
desire, for the latter has its principles a priori in concepts of           
reason. Logical estimates of nature, however, stand on a different          
footing. They deal with cases in which experience presents a                
conformity to law in things, which the understanding's general concept      
of the sensible is no longer adequate to render intelligible or             
explicable, and in which judgement may have recourse to itself for a        
principle of the reference of the natural thing to the unknowable           
supersensible and, indeed, must employ some such principle, though          
with a regard only to itself and the knowledge of nature. For in these      
cases the application of such an a priori principle for the                 
cognition of what is in the world is both possible and necessary,           
and withal opens out prospects which are profitable for practical           
reason. But here there is no immediate reference to the feeling of          
pleasure or displeasure. But this is precisely the riddle in the            
principle of judgement that necessitates a separate division for            
this faculty in the critique-for there was nothing to prevent the           
formation of logical estimates according to concepts (from which no         
immediate conclusion can ever be drawn to the feeling of pleasure or        
displeasure) having been treated, with a critical statement of its          
limitations, in an appendage to the theoretical part of philosophy.         
                                                     {PREFACE ^paragraph 10}
  The present investigation of taste, as a faculty of aesthetic             
judgement, not being undertaken with a view to the formation or             
culture of taste (which will pursue its course in the future, as in         
the past, independently of such inquiries), but being merely                
directed to its transcendental aspects, I feel assured of its               
indulgent criticism in respect of any shortcomings on that score.           
But in all that is relevant to the transcendental aspect it must be         
prepared to stand the test of the most rigorous examination. Yet            
even here I venture to hope that the difficulty of unravelling a            
problem so involved in its nature may serve as an excuse for a certain      
amount of hardly avoidable obscurity in its solution, provided that         
the accuracy of our statement of the principle is proved with all           
requisite clearness. I admit that the mode of deriving the phenomena        
of judgement from that principle has not all the lucidity that is           
rightly demanded elsewhere, where the subject is cognition by               
concepts, and that I believe I have in fact attained in the second          
part of this work.                                                          
  With this, then, I bring my entire critical undertaking to a              
close. I shall hasten to the doctrinal part, in order, as far as            
possible, to snatch from my advancing years what time may yet be            
favourable to the task. It is obvious that no separate division of          
doctrine is reserved for the faculty of judgement, seeing that, with        
judgement, critique takes the place of theory; but, following the           
division of philosophy into theoretical and practical, and of pure          
philosophy in the same way, the whole ground will be covered by the         
metaphysics of nature and of morals.                                        
-                                                                           
                                                                            
INTRO                                                                       
                         INTRODUCTION.                                      
                  I. Division of Philosophy.                                
-                                                                           
  Philosophy may be said to contain the principles of the rational          
cognition that concepts afford us of things (not merely, as with            
logic, the principles of the form of thought in general irrespective        
of the objects), and, thus interpreted, the course, usually adopted,        
of dividing it into theoretical and practical is perfectly sound.           
But this makes imperative a specific distinction on the part of the         
concepts by which the principles of this rational cognition get             
their object assigned to them, for if the concepts are not distinct         
they fail to justify a division, which always presupposes that the          
principles belonging to the rational cognition of the several parts of      
the science in question are themselves mutually exclusive.                  
  Now there are but two kinds of concepts, and these yield a                
corresponding number of distinct principles of the possibility of           
their objects. The concepts referred to are those of nature and that        
of freedom. By the first of these, a theoretical cognition from a           
priori principles becomes possible. In respect of such cognition,           
however, the second, by its very concept, imports no more than a            
negative principle (that of simple antithesis), while for the               
determination of the will, on the other hand, it establishes                
fundamental principles which enlarge the scope of its activity, and         
which on that account are called practical. Hence the division of           
philosophy falls properly into two parts, quite distinct in their           
principles-a theoretical, as philosophy of nature, and a practical, as      
philosophy of morals (for this is what the practical legislation of         
reason by the concept of freedom is called). Hitherto, however, in the      
application of these expressions to the division of the different           
principles, and with them to the division of philosophy, a gross            
misuse of the terms has prevailed; for what is practical according          
to concepts of nature bas been taken as identical with what is              
practical according to the concept of freedom, with the result that         
a division has been made under these heads of theoretical and               
practical, by which, in effect, there has been no division at all           
(seeing that both parts might have similar principles).                     
  The will-for this is what is said-is the faculty of desire and, as        
such, is just one of the many natural causes in the world, the one,         
namely, which acts by concepts; and whatever is represented as              
possible (or necessary) through the efficacy of will is called              
practically possible (or necessary): the intention being to                 
distinguish its possibility (or necessity) from the physical                
possibility or necessity of an effect the causality of whose cause          
is not determined to its production by concepts (but rather, as with        
lifeless matter, by mechanism, and, as with the lower animals, by           
instinct). Now, the question in respect of the practical faculty:           
whether, that is to say, the concept, by which the causality of the         
will gets its rule, is a concept of nature or of freedom, is here left      
quite open.                                                                 
  The latter distinction, however, is essential. For, let the               
concept determining the causality be a concept of nature, and then the      
principles are technically-practical; but, let it be a concept of           
freedom, and they are morally-practical. Now, in the division of a          
rational science the difference between objects that require different      
principles for their cognition is the difference on which everything        
turns. Hence technically-practical principles belong to theoretical         
philosophy (natural science), whereas those morally-practical alone         
form the second part, that is, practical philosophy (ethical science).      
                                                        {INTRO ^paragraph 5}
  All technically-practical rules (i.e., those of art and skill             
generally, or even of prudence, as a skill in exercising an                 
influence over men and their wills) must, so far as their principles        
rest upon concepts, be reckoned only as corollaries to theoretical          
philosophy. For they only touch the possibility of things according to      
concepts of nature, and this embraces, not alone the means                  
discoverable in nature for the purpose, but even the will itself (as a      
faculty of desire, and consequently a natural faculty), so far as it        
is determinable on these rules by natural motives. Still these              
practical rules are not called laws (like physical laws), but only          
precepts. This is due to the fact that the will does not stand              
simply under the natural concept, but also under the concept of             
freedom. In the latter connection its principles are called laws,           
and these principles, with the addition of what follows them, alone         
constitute the second at practical part of philosophy.                      
  The solution of the problems of pure geometry is not allocated to         
a special part of that science, nor does the art of land-surveying          
merit the name of practical, in contradistinction to pure, as a second      
part of the general science of geometry, and with equally little, or        
perhaps less, right can the mechanical or chemical art of experiment        
or of observation be ranked as a practical part of the science of           
nature, or, in fine, domestic, agricultural, or political economy, the      
art of social intercourse, the principles of dietetics, or even             
general instruction as to the attainment of happiness, or as much as        
the control of the inclinations or the restraining of the affections        
with a view thereto, be denominated practical philosophy-not to             
mention forming these latter in a second part of philosophy in              
general. For, between them all, the above contain nothing more than         
rules of skill, which are thus only technically practical-the skill         
being directed to producing an effect which is possible according to        
natural concepts of causes and effects. As these concepts belong to         
theoretical philosophy, they are subject to those precepts as mere          
corollaries of theoretical philosophy (i.e., as corollaries of natural      
science), and so cannot claim any place in any special philosophy           
called practical. On the other hand, the morally practical precepts,        
which are founded entirely on the concept of freedom, to the                
complete exclusion of grounds taken from nature for the                     
determination of the will, form quite a special kind of precepts.           
These, too, like the rules obeyed by nature, are, without                   
qualification, called laws-though they do not, like the latter, rest        
on sensible conditions, but upon a supersensible principle-and they         
must needs have a separate part of philosophy allotted to them as           
their own, corresponding to the theoretical part, and termed practical      
philosophy capable                                                          
  Hence it is evident that a complex of practical precepts furnished        
by philosophy does not form a special part of philosophy,                   
co-ordinate with the theoretical, by reason of its precepts being           
practical-for that they might be, notwithstanding that their                
principles were derived wholly from the theoretical knowledge of            
nature (as technically-practical rules). But an adequate reason only        
exists where their principle, being in no way borrowed from the             
concept of nature, which is always sensibly conditioned, rests              
consequently on the supersensible, which the concept of freedom             
alone makes cognizable by means of its formal laws, and where,              
therefore, they are morally-practical, i. e., not merely precepts           
and its and rules in this or that interest, but laws independent of         
all antecedent reference to ends or aims.                                   
-                                                                           
            II. The Realm of Philosophy in General.                         
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 10}
-                                                                           
  The employment of our faculty of cognition from principles, and with      
it philosophy, is coextensive with the applicability of a priori            
concepts.                                                                   
  Now a division of the complex of all the objects to which those           
concepts are referred for the purpose, where possible, of compassing        
their knowledge, may be made according to the varied competence or          
incompetence of our faculty in that connection.                             
  Concepts, so far as they are referred to objects apart from the           
question of whether knowledge of them is possible or not, have their        
field, which is determined simply by the relation in which their            
object stands to our faculty of cognition in general. The part of this      
field in which knowledge is possible for us is a territory                  
(territorium) for these concepts and the requisite cognitive                
faculty. The part of the territory over which they exercise                 
legislative authority is the realm (ditio) of these concepts, and           
their appropriate cognitive faculty. Empirical concepts have,               
therefore, their territory, doubtless, in nature as the complex of all      
sensible objects, but they have no realm (only a dwelling-place,            
domicilium), for, although they are formed according to law, they           
are not themselves legislative, but the rules founded on them are           
empirical and, consequently, contingent.                                    
  Our entire faculty of cognition has two realms, that of natural           
concepts and that of the concept of freedom, for through both it            
prescribes laws a priori. In accordance with this distinction, then,        
philosophy is divisible into theoretical and practical. But the             
territory upon which its realm is established, and over which it            
exercises its legislative authority, is still always confined to the        
complex of the objects of all possible experience, taken as no more         
than mere phenomena, for otherwise legislation by the understanding in      
respect of them is unthinkable.                                             
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 15}
  The function of prescribing laws by means of concepts of nature is        
discharged by understanding and is theoretical. That of prescribing         
laws by means of the concept of freedom is discharged by reason and is      
merely practical. It is only in the practical sphere that reason can        
prescribe laws; in respect of theoretical knowledge (of nature) it can      
only (as by the understanding advised in the law) deduce from given         
logical consequences, which still always remain restricted to               
nature. But we cannot reverse this and say that where rules are             
practical reason is then and there legislative, since the rules             
might be technically practical.                                             
  Understanding and reason, therefore, have two distinct jurisdictions      
over one and the same territory of experience. But neither can              
interfere with the other. For the concept of freedom just as little         
disturbs the legislation of nature, as the concept of nature                
influences legislation through the concept of freedom. That it is           
possible for us at least to think without contradiction of both             
these jurisdictions, and their appropriate faculties, as co-existing        
in the same subject, was shown by the Critique of Pure Reason, since        
it disposed of the objections on the other side by detecting their          
dialectical illusion.                                                       
  Still, how does it happen that these two different realms do not          
form one realm, seeing that, while they do not limit each other in          
their legislation, they continually do so in their effects in the           
sensible world? The explanation lies in the fact that the concept of        
nature represents its objects in intuition doubtless, yet not as            
things in-themselves, but as mere phenomena, whereas the concept of         
freedom represents in its object what is no doubt a thing-in-itself,        
but it does not make it intuitable, and further that neither the one        
nor the other is capable, therefore, of furnishing a theoretical            
cognition of its object (or even of the thinking subject) as a              
thing-in-itself, or, as this would be, of the supersensible idea of         
which has certainly to be introduced as the basis of the possibility        
of all those objects of experience, although it cannot itself ever          
be elevated or extended into a cognition.                                   
  Our entire cognitive faculty is, therefore, presented with an             
unbounded, but, also, inaccessible field-the field of the                   
supersensible-in which we seek in vain for a territory, and on              
which, therefore, we can have no realm for theoretical cognition, be        
it for concepts of understanding or of reason. This field we must           
indeed occupy with ideas in the interest as well of the theoretical as      
the practical employment of reason, but, in connection with the laws        
arising from the concept of freedom, we cannot procure for these ideas      
any but practical reality, which, accordingly, fails to advance our         
theoretical cognition one step towards the supersensible.                   
  Albeit, then, between the realm of the natural concept, as the            
sensible, and the realm of the concept of freedom, as the                   
supersensible, there is a great gulf fixed, so that it is not possible      
to pass from the to the latter (by means of the theoretical employment      
of reason), just as if they were so many separate worlds, the first of      
which is powerless to exercise influence on the second: still the           
latter is meant to influence the former-that is to say, the concept of      
freedom is meant to actualize in the sensible world the end proposed        
by its laws; and nature must consequently also be capable of being          
regarded in such a way that in the conformity to law of its form it at      
least harmonizes with the possibility of the ends to be effectuated in      
it according to the laws of freedom. There must, therefore, be a            
ground of the unity of the supersensible that lies at the basis of          
nature, with what the concept of freedom contains in a practical            
way, and although the concept of this ground neither theoretically nor      
practically attains to a knowledge of it, and so has no peculiar realm      
of its own, still it renders possible the transition from the mode          
of thought according to the principles of the one to that according to      
the principles of the other.                                                
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 20}
-                                                                           
       III. The Critique of Judgement as a means of                         
           connecting the two Parts of Philosophy                           
                       in a whole.                                          
-                                                                           
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 25}
  The critique which deals with what our cognitive faculties are            
capable of yielding a priori has properly speaking no realm in respect      
of objects; for it is not a doctrine, its sole business being to            
investigate whether, having regard to the general bearings of our           
faculties, a doctrine is possible by their means, and if so, how.           
Its field extends to all their pretentions, with a view to confining        
them within their legitimate bounds. But what is shut out of the            
division of philosophy may still be admitted as a principal part            
into the general critique of our faculty of pure cognition, in the          
event, namely, of its containing principles which are not in                
themselves available either for theoretical or practical employment.        
  Concepts of nature contain the ground of all theoretical cognition a      
priori and rest, as we saw, upon the legislative authority of               
understanding. The concept of freedom contains the ground of all            
sensuously unconditioned practical precepts a priori, and rests upon        
that of reason. Both faculties, therefore, besides their application        
in point of logical form to principles of whatever origin, have, in         
addition, their own peculiar jurisdiction in the matter of their            
content, and so, there being no further (a priori) jurisdiction             
above them, the division of philosophy into theoretical and                 
practical is justified.                                                     
  But there is still further in the family of our higher cognitive          
faculties a middle term between understanding and reason. This is           
judgement, of which we may reasonably presume by analogy that it may        
likewise contain, if not a special authority to prescribe laws,             
still a principle peculiar to itself upon which laws are sought,            
although one merely subjective a priori. This principle, even if it         
has no field of objects appropriate to it as its realm, may still have      
some territory or other with a certain character, for which just            
this very principle alone may be valid.                                     
  But in addition to the above considerations there is yet (to judge        
by analogy) a further ground, upon which judgement may be brought into      
line with another arrangement of our powers of representation, and one      
that appears to be of even greater importance than that of its kinship      
with the family of cognitive faculties. For all faculties of the soul,      
or capacities, are reducible to three, which do not admit of any            
further derivation from a common ground: the faculty of knowledge, the      
feeling of pleasure or displeasure, and the faculty of desire.* For         
the faculty of cognition understanding alone is legislative, if (as         
must be the case where it is considered on its own account free of          
confusion with the faculty of desire) this faculty, as that of              
theoretical cognition, is referred to nature, in respect of which           
alone (as phenomenon) it is possible for us to prescribe laws by means      
of a priori concepts of nature, which are properly pure concepts of         
understanding. For the faculty of desire, as a higher faculty               
operating under the concept of freedom, only reason (in which alone         
this concept has a place) prescribes laws a priori. Now between the         
faculties of knowledge and desire stands the feeling of pleasure, just      
as judgement is intermediate between understanding and reason. Hence        
we may, provisionally at least, assume that judgement likewise              
contains an a priori principle of its own, and that, since pleasure or      
displeasure is necessarily combined with the faculty of desire (be          
it antecedent to its principle, as with the lower desires, or, as with      
the higher, only supervening upon its determination by the moral law),      
it will effect a transition from the faculty of pure knowledge,             
i.e., from the realm of concepts of nature, to that of the concept          
of freedom, just as i its logical employment it makes possible the          
transition from understanding to reason.                                    
-                                                                           
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 30}
  *Where one has reason to suppose that a relation subsists between         
concepts that are used as empirical principles and the faculty of pure      
cognition a priori, it is worth while attempting, in consideration          
of this connection, to give them a transcendental definition-a              
definition, that is, by pure categories, so far as these by themselves      
adequately indicate the distinction of the concept in question from         
others. This course follows that of the mathematician, who leaves           
the empirical data of his problem indeterminate, and only brings their      
relation in pure synthesis under the concepts of pure arithmetic,           
and thus generalizes his solution.-I have been taken to task for            
adopting a similar procedure and fault had been found with my               
definition of the faculty of desire as a faculty which by means of its      
representations is the cause of the cause of the actuality of the           
objects of those representations: for mere wishes would still be            
desires, and yet in their case every one is ready to abandon all claim      
to being able by means of them alone to call their object into              
existence. -But this proves no more than the presence of desires in         
man by which he is in contradiction with himself. For in such a case        
he seeks the production of the object by means of his representation        
alone, without any hope of its being effectual, since he is                 
conscious that his mechanical powers (if I may so call those which are      
not psychological), which would have to be determined by that               
representation, are either unequal to the task of realizing the object      
(by the intervention of means, therefore) or else are addressed to          
what is quite impossible, as, for example, to undo the past (O mihi         
praeteritos, etc.) or, to be able to annihilate the interval that,          
with intolerable delay, divides us from the wished for moment. -Now,        
conscious as we are in such fantastic desires of the inefficiency of        
our representations (or even of their futility), as causes of their         
objects, there is still involved in every wish a reference of the same      
as cause, and therefore the representation of its causality, and            
this is especially discernible where the wish, as longing, is an            
affection. For such affections, since they dilate the heart and render      
it inert and thus exhaust its powers, show that a strain is kept on         
being exerted and re-exerted on these powers by the representations,        
but that the mind is allowed continually to relapse and get languid         
upon recognition of the impossibility before it. Even prayers for           
the aversion of great, and, so far as we can see, inevitable evils,         
and many superstitious means for attaining ends impossible of               
attainment by natural means, prove the causal reference of                  
representations to their objects-a causality which not even the             
consciousness of inefficiency for producing the effect can deter            
from straining towards it. But why our nature should be furnished with      
a propensity to consciously vain desires is a teleological problem          
of anthropology. It would seem that were we not to be determined to         
the exertion of our power before we had assured ourselves of the            
efficiency of our faculty for producing an object, our power would          
remain to a large extent unused. For as a rule we only first learn          
to know our powers by making trial of them. This deceit of vain             
desires is therefore only the result of a beneficent disposition in         
our nature.                                                                 
-                                                                           
  Hence, despite the fact of philosophy being only divisible into           
two principal parts, the theoretical and the practical, and despite         
the fact of all that we may have to say of the special principles of        
judgement having to be assigned to its theoretical part, i.e., to           
rational cognition according to concepts of nature: still the Critique      
of Pure Reason, which must settle this whole question before the above      
system is taken in hand, so as to substantiate its possibility,             
consists of three parts: the Critique of pure understanding, of pure        
judgement, and of pure reason, which faculties are called pure on           
the ground of their being legislative a priori.                             
-                                                                           
         IV. Judgement as a Faculty by which Laws are                       
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 35}
                     prescribed a priori.                                   
-                                                                           
  Judgement in general is the faculty of thinking the particular as         
contained under the universal. If the universal (the rule,                  
principle, or law) is given, then the judgement which subsumes the          
particular under it is determinant. This is so even where such a            
judgement is transcendental and, as such, provides the conditions a         
priori in conformity with which alone subsumption under that universal      
can be effected. If, however, only the particular is given and the          
universal has to be found for it, then the judgement is simply              
reflective.                                                                 
  The determinant judgement determines under universal                      
transcendental laws furnished by understanding and is subsumptive           
only; the law is marked out for it a priori, and it has no need to          
devise a law for its own guidance to enable it to subordinate the           
particular in nature to the universal. But there are such manifold          
forms of nature, so many modifications, as it were, of the universal        
transcendental concepts of nature, left undetermined by the laws            
furnished by pure understanding a priori as above mentioned, and for        
the reason that these laws only touch the general possibility of a          
nature (as an object of sense), that there must needs also be laws          
in this behalf. These laws, being empirical, may be contingent as           
far as the light of our understanding goes, but still, if they are          
to be called laws (as the concept of a nature requires), they must          
be regarded as necessary on a principle, unknown though it be to us,        
of the unity of the manifold. The reflective judgement which is             
compelled to ascend from the particular in nature to the universal          
stands, therefore, in need of a principle. This principle it cannot         
borrow from experience, because what it has to do is to establish just      
the unity of all empirical principles under higher, though likewise         
empirical, principles, and thence the possibility of the systematic         
subordination of higher and lower. Such a transcendental principle,         
therefore, the reflective judgement can only give as a law from and to      
itself. It cannot derive it from any other quarter (as it would then        
be a determinant judgement). Nor can it prescribe it to nature, for         
reflection on the laws of nature adjusts itself to nature, and not          
nature to the conditions according to which we strive to obtain a           
concept of it-a concept that is quite contingent in respect of these        
conditions.                                                                 
  Now the principle sought can only be this: as universal laws of           
nature have their ground in our understanding, which prescribes them        
to nature (though only according to the universal concept of it as          
nature), particular empirical laws must be regarded, in respect of          
that which is left undetermined in them by these universal laws,            
according to a unity such as they would have if an understanding            
(though it be not ours) had supplied them for the benefit of our            
cognitive faculties, so as to render possible a system of experience        
according to particular natural laws. This is not to be taken as            
implying that such an understanding must be actually assumed (for it        
is only the reflective judgement which avails itself of this idea as a      
principle for the purpose of reflection and not for determining             
anything); but this faculty rather gives by this means a law to itself      
alone and not to nature.                                                    
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 40}
  Now the concept of an object, so far as it contains at the same time      
the ground of the actuality of this object, is called its end, and the      
agreement of a thing with that constitution of things which is only         
possible according to ends, is called the finality of its form.             
Accordingly the principle of judgement, in respect of the form of           
the things of nature under empirical laws generally, is the finality        
of nature in its multiplicity. In other words, by this concept              
nature is represented as if an understanding contained the ground of        
the unity of the manifold of its empirical laws.                            
  The finality of nature is, therefore, a particular a priori concept,      
which bas its origin solely in the reflective judgement. For we cannot      
ascribe to the products of nature anything like a reference of              
nature in them to ends, but we can only make use of this concept to         
reflect upon them in respect of the nexus of phenomena in nature-a          
nexus given according to empirical laws. Furthermore, this concept          
is entirely different from practical finality (in human art or even         
morals), though it is doubtless thought after this analogy.                 
-                                                                           
       V. The Principle of the formal finality of Nature is a               
              transcendental Principle of Judgement.                        
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 45}
-                                                                           
  A transcendental principle is one through which we represent a            
priori the universal condition under which alone things can become          
objects of our cognition generally. A principle, on the other band, is      
called metaphysical where it represents a priori the condition under        
which alone objects whose concept has to be given empirically may           
become further determined a priori. Thus the principle of the               
cognition of bodies as substances, and as changeable substances, is         
transcendental where the statement is that their change must have a         
cause: but it is metaphysical where it asserts that their change            
must have an external cause. For, in the first case, bodies need            
only be thought through ontological predicates (pure concepts of            
understanding) e.g., as substance, to enable the proposition to be          
cognized a priori; whereas, in the second case, the empirical               
concept of a body (as a movable thing in space) must be introduced          
to support the proposition, although, once this is done, it may be          
seen quite a priori that the latter predicate (movement only by             
means of an external cause) applies to body. In this way, as I shall        
show presently, the principle of the finality of nature (in the             
multiplicity of its empirical laws) is a transcendental principle. For      
the concept of objects, regarded as standing under this principle,          
is only the pure concept of objects of possible empirical cognition         
generally, and involves nothing empirical. On the other band, the           
principle of practical finality, implied in the idea of the                 
determination of a free will, would be a metaphysical principle,            
because the concept of a faculty of desire, as will, has to be given        
empirically, i.e., is not included among transcendental predicates.         
But both these principles are, none the less, not empirical, but a          
priori principles; because no further experience is required for the        
synthesis of the predicate with the empirical concept of the subject        
of their judgements, but it may be apprehended quite a priori.              
  That the concept of a finality of nature belongs to transcendental        
principles is abundantly evident from the maxims of judgement upon          
which we rely a priori in the investigation of nature, and which yet        
have to do with no more than the possibility of experience, and             
consequently of the knowledge of nature-but of nature not merely in         
a general way, but as determined by a manifold of particular laws.          
These maxims crop up frequently enough in the course of this                
science, though only in a scattered way. They are aphorisms of              
metaphysical wisdom, making their appearance in a number of rules           
the necessity of which cannot be demonstrated from concepts. "Nature        
takes the shortest way (lex parsimoniae); yet it makes no leap, either      
in the sequence of its changes, or in the juxtaposition of                  
specifically different forms (lex continui in natura); its vast             
variety in empirical laws is for all that, unity under a few                
principles (principia praeter necessitatem non sunt multiplicanda)";        
and so forth.                                                               
  If we propose to assign the origin of these elementary rules, and         
attempt to do so on psychological lines, we go straight in the teeth        
of their sense. For they tell us, not what happens, i.e., according to      
what rule our powers of judgement actually discharge their                  
functions, and how we judge, but how we ought to judge; and we              
cannot get this logical objective necessity where the principles are        
merely empirical. Hence the finality of nature for our cognitive            
faculties and their employment, which manifestly radiates from them,        
is a transcendental principle of judgements, and so needs also a            
transcendental deduction, by means of which the ground for this mode        
of judging must be traced to the a priori sources of knowledge.             
  Now, looking at the grounds of the possibility of an experience, the      
first thing, of course, that meets us is something necessary-namely,        
the universal laws apart from which nature in general (as an object of      
sense) cannot be thought. These rest on the categories, applied to the      
formal conditions of all intuition possible for us, so far as it is         
also given a priori. Under these laws, judgement is determinant; for        
it bas nothing else to do than to subsume under given laws. For             
instance, understanding says: all change has its cause (universal           
law of nature); transcendental judgement has nothing further to do          
than to furnish a priori the condition of subsumption under the             
concept of understanding placed before it: this we get in the               
succession of the determinations of one and the same thing. Now for         
nature in general, as an object of possible experience, that law is         
cognized as absolutely necessary. But besides this formal                   
time-condition, the objects of empirical cognition are determined, or,      
so far as we can judge a priori, are determinable, in divers ways,          
so that specifically differentiated natures, over and above what            
they have in common as things of nature in general, are further             
capable of being causes in an infinite variety of ways; and each of         
these modes must, on the concept of a cause in general, have its rule,      
which is a law, and, consequently, imports necessity: although owing        
to the constitution and limitations of our faculties of cognition we        
may entirely fail to see this necessity. Accordingly, in respect of         
nature's merely empirical laws, we must think in nature a                   
possibility of an endless multiplicity of empirical laws, which yet         
are contingent so far as our insight goes, i.e., cannot be cognized         
a priori. In respect of these we estimate the unity of nature               
according to empirical laws, and the possibility of the unity of            
experience, as a system according to empirical laws, to be contingent.      
But, now, such a unity is one which must be necessarily presupposed         
and assumed, as otherwise we should not have a thoroughgoing                
connection of empirical cognition in a whole of experience. For the         
universal laws of nature, while providing, certainly, for such a            
connection among things generically, as things of nature in general,        
do not do so for them specifically as such particular things of             
nature. Hence judgement is compelled, for its own guidance, to adopt        
it as an a priori principle, that what is for human insight contingent      
in the particular (empirical) laws of nature contains nevertheless          
unity of law in the synthesis of its manifold in an intrinsically           
possible experience-unfathomable, though still thinkable, as such           
unity may, no doubt, be for us. Consequently, as the unity of law in a      
synthesis, which is cognized by us in obedience to a necessary aim          
(a need of understanding), though recognized at the same time as            
contingent, is represented as a finality of objects (here of                
nature), so judgement, which, in respect of things under possible (yet      
to be discovered) empirical laws, is merely reflective, must regard         
nature in respect of the latter according to a principle of finality        
for our cognitive faculty, which then finds expression in the above         
maxims of judgement. Now this transcendental concept of a finality          
of nature is neither a concept of nature nor of freedom, since it           
attributes nothing at all to the object, i.e., to nature, but only          
represents the unique mode in which we must proceed in our                  
reflection upon the objects of nature with a view to getting a              
thoroughly interconnected whole of experience, and so is a                  
subjective principle, i.e., maxim, of judgement. For this reason, too,      
just as if it were a lucky chance that favoured us, we are rejoiced         
(properly speaking, relieved of a want) where we meet with such             
systematic unity under merely empirical laws: although we must              
necessarily assume the presence of such a unity, apart from any             
ability on our part to apprehend or prove its existence.                    
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 50}
  In order to convince ourselves of the correctness of this                 
deduction of the concept before us, and the necessity of assuming it        
as a transcendental principle of cognition, let us just bethink             
ourselves of the magnitude of the task. We have to form a connected         
experience from given perceptions of a nature containing a maybe            
endless multiplicity of empirical laws, and this problem has its            
seat a priori in our understanding. This understanding is no doubt a        
priori in possession of universal laws of nature, apart from which          
nature would be incapable of being an object of experience at all. But      
over and above this it needs a certain order of nature in its               
particular rules which are only capable of being brought to its             
knowledge empirically, and which, so far as it is concerned are             
contingent. These rules, without which we would have no means of            
advance from the universal analogy of a possible experience in general      
to a particular, must be regarded by understanding as laws, i.e., as        
necessary-for otherwise they would not form an order of                     
nature-though it be unable to cognize or ever get an insight into           
their necessity. Albeit, then, it can determine nothing a priori in         
respect of these (objects), it must, in pursuit of such empirical           
so-called laws, lay at the basis of all reflection upon them an a           
priori principle, to the effect, namely, that a cognizable order of         
nature is possible according to them. A principle of this kind is           
expressed in the following propositions. There is in nature a               
subordination of genera and species comprehensible by us: Each of           
these genera again approximates to the others on a common principle,        
so that a transition may be possible from one to the other, and             
thereby to a higher genus: While it seems at outset unavoidable for         
our understanding to assume for the specific variety of natural             
operations a like number of various kinds of causality, yet these           
may all be reduced to a small number of principles, the quest for           
which is our business; and so forth. This adaptation of nature to           
our cognitive faculties is presupposed a priori by judgement on behalf      
of its reflection upon it according to empirical laws. But                  
understanding all the while recognizes it objectively as contingent,        
and it is merely judgement that attributes it to nature as                  
transcendental finality, i.e., a finality in respect of the                 
subject's faculty of cognition. For, were it not for this                   
presupposition, we should have no order of nature in accordance with        
empirical laws, and, consequently, no guiding-thread for an experience      
that has to be brought to bear upon these in all their variety, or for      
an investigation of them.                                                   
  For it is quite conceivable that, despite all the uniformity of           
the things of nature according to universal laws, without which we          
would not have the form of general empirical knowledge at all, the          
specific variety of the empirical laws of nature, with their                
effects, might still be so great as to make it impossible for our           
understanding to discover in nature an intelligible order, to divide        
its products into genera and species so as to avail ourselves of the        
principles of explanation and comprehension of one for explaining           
and interpreting another, and out of material coming to hand in such        
confusion (properly speaking only infinitely multiform and ill-adapted      
to our power-of apprehension) to make a consistent context of               
experience.                                                                 
  Thus judgement, also, is equipped with an a priori principle for the      
possibility of nature, but only in a subjective respect. By means of        
this it prescribes a law, not to nature (as autonomy), but to itself        
(as heautonomy), to guide its reflection upon nature. This law may          
be called the law of the specification of nature in respect of its          
empirical laws. It is not one cognized a priori in nature, but              
judgement adopts it in the interests of a natural order, cognizable by      
our understanding, in the division which it makes of nature's               
universal laws when it seeks to subordinate to them a variety of            
particular laws. So when it is said that nature specifies its               
universal laws on a principle of finality for our cognitive faculties,      
i.e., of suitability for the human understanding and its necessary          
function of finding the universal for the particular presented to it        
by perception, and again for varieties (which are, of course, common        
for each species) connection in the unity of principle, we do not           
thereby either prescribe a law to nature, or learn one from it by           
observation-although the principle in question may be confirmed by          
this means. For it is not a principle of the determinant but merely of      
the reflective judgement. All that is intended is that, no matter what      
is the order and disposition of nature in respect of its universal          
laws, we must investigate its empirical laws throughout on that             
principle and the maxims founded thereon, because only so far as            
that principle applies can we make any headway in the employment of         
our understanding in experience, or gain knowledge.                         
-                                                                           
         VI. The Association of the Feeling of Pleasure                     
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 55}
           with the Concept of the Finality of Nature.                      
-                                                                           
  The conceived harmony of nature in the manifold of its particular         
laws with our need of finding universality of principles for it             
must, so far as our insight goes, be deemed contingent, but withal          
indispensable for the requirements of our understanding, and,               
consequently, a finality by which nature is in accord with our aim,         
but only so far as this is directed to knowledge. The universal laws        
of understanding, which are equally laws of nature, are, although           
arising from spontaneity, just as necessary for nature as the laws          
of motion applicable to matter. Their origin does not presuppose any        
regard to our cognitive faculties, seeing that it is only by their          
means that we first come by any conception of the meaning of a              
knowledge of things (of nature), and they of necessity apply to nature      
as object of our cognition in general. But it is contingent, so far as      
we can see, that the order of nature in its particular laws, with           
their wealth of at least possible variety and heterogeneity                 
transcending all our powers of comprehension, should still in actual        
fact be commensurate with these powers. To find out this order is an        
undertaking on the part of our understanding, which pursues it with         
a regard to a necessary end of its own, that, namely, of introducing        
into nature unity of principle. This end must, then, be attributed          
to nature by judgement, since no law can be here prescribed to it by        
understanding.                                                              
  The attainment of every aim is coupled with a feeling of pleasure.        
Now where such attainment has for its condition a representation a          
priori-as here a principle for the reflective judgement in general-the      
feeling of pleasure also is determined by a ground which is a priori        
and valid for all men: and that, too, merely by virtue of the               
reference of the object to our faculty of cognition. As the concept of      
finality here takes no cognizance whatever of the faculty of desire,        
it differs entirely from all practical finality of nature.                  
  As a matter of fact, we do not, and cannot, find in ourselves the         
slightest effect on the feeling of pleasure from the coincidence of         
perceptions with the laws in accordance with the universal concepts of      
nature (the categories), since in their case understanding necessarily      
follows the bent of its own nature without ulterior aim. But, while         
this is so, the discovery, on the other hand, that two or more              
empirical heterogeneous laws of nature are allied under one                 
principle that embraces them both, is the ground of a very appreciable      
pleasure, often even of admiration, and such, too, as does not wear         
off even though we are already familiar enough with its object. It          
is true that we no longer notice any decided pleasure in the                
comprehensibility of nature, or in the unity of its divisions into          
genera and species, without which the empirical concepts, that              
afford us our knowledge of nature in its particular laws, would not be      
possible. Still it is certain that the pleasure appeared in due             
course, and only by reason of the most ordinary experience being            
impossible without it, bas it become gradually fused with simple            
cognition, and no longer arrests particular attention. Something,           
then, that makes us attentive in our estimate of nature to its              
finality for our understanding-an endeavour to bring, where                 
possible, its heterogeneous laws under higher, though still always          
empirical, laws-is required, in order that, on meeting with success,        
pleasure may be felt in this their accord with our cognitive                
faculty, which accord is regarded by us as purely contingent. As            
against this, a representation of nature would be altogether                
displeasing to us, were we to be forewarned by it that, on the least        
investigation carried beyond the commonest experience, we should            
come in contact with such a heterogeneity of its laws as would make         
the union of its particular laws under universal empirical laws             
impossible for our understanding. For this would conflict with the          
principle of the subjectively final specification of nature in its          
genera, and with our own reflective judgement in respect thereof.           
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 60}
  Yet this presupposition of judgement is so indeterminate on the           
question of the extent of the prevalence of that ideal finality of          
nature for our cognitive faculties, that if we are told that a more         
searching or enlarged knowledge of nature, derived from observation,        
must eventually bring us into contact with a multiplicity of laws that      
no human understanding could reduce to a principle, we can reconcile        
ourselves to the thought. But still we listen more gladly to others         
who hold out to us the hope that the more intimately we come to know        
the secrets of nature, or the better we are able to compare it with         
external members as yet unknown to us, the more simple shall we find        
it in its principles, and the further our experience advances the more      
harmonious shall we find it in the apparent heterogeneity of its            
empirical laws. For our judgement makes it imperative upon us to            
proceed on the principle of the conformity of nature to our faculty of      
cognition, so far as that principle extends, without deciding-for           
the rule is not given to us by a determinant judgement-whether              
bounds are anywhere set to it or not. For, while in respect of the          
rational employment of our cognitive faculty, bounds may be definitely      
determined, in the empirical field no such determination of bounds          
is possible.                                                                
-                                                                           
          VII. The Aesthetic Representation of the                          
                     Finality of Nature.                                    
-                                                                           
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 65}
  That which is purely subjective in the representation of an               
object, i.e., what constitutes its reference to the subject, not to         
the object, is its aesthetic quality. On the other hand, that which in      
such a representation serves, or is available, for the determination        
of the object (for or purpose of knowledge), is its logical                 
validity. In the cognition of an object of sense, both sides are            
presented conjointly. In the sense-representation of external               
things, the quality of space in which we intuite them is the merely         
subjective side of my representation of them (by which what the things      
are in themselves as objects is left quite open), and it is on account      
of that reference that the object in being intuited in space is also        
thought merely as phenomenon. But despite its purely subjective             
quality, space is still a constituent of the knowledge of things as         
phenomena. Sensation (here external) also agrees in expressing a            
merely subjective side of our representations of external things,           
but one which is properly their matter (through which we are given          
something with real existence), just as space is the mere a priori          
form of the possibility of their intuition; and so sensation is,            
none the less, also employed in the cognition of external objects.          
  But that subjective side of a representation which is incapable of        
becoming an element of cognition, is the pleasure or displeasure            
connected with it; for through it I cognize nothing in the object of        
the representation, although it may easily be the result of the             
operation of some cognition or other. Now the finality of a thing,          
so far as represented in our perception of it, is in no way a               
quality of the object itself (for a quality of this kind is not one         
that can be perceived), although it may be inferred from a cognition        
of things. In the finality, therefore, which is prior to the cognition      
of an object, and which, even apart from any desire to make use of the      
representation of it for the purpose of a cognition, is yet                 
immediately connected with it, we have the subjective quality               
belonging to it that is incapable of becoming a constituent of              
knowledge. Hence we only apply the term final to the object on account      
of its representation being immediately coupled with the feeling of         
pleasure: and this representation itself is an aesthetic                    
representation of the finality. The only question is whether such a         
representation of finality exists at all.                                   
  If pleasure is connected with the mere apprehension (apprehensio) of      
the form of an object of intuition, apart from any reference it may         
have to a concept for the purpose of a definite cognition, this does        
not make the representation referable to the object, but solely to the      
subject. In such a case, the pleasure can express nothing but the           
conformity of the object to the cognitive faculties brought into            
play in the reflective judgement, and so far as they are in play,           
and hence merely a subjective formal finality of the object. For            
that apprehension of forms in the imagination can never take place          
without the reflective judgement, even when it has no intention of          
so doing, comparing them at least with its faculty of referring             
intuitions to concepts. If, now, in this comparison, imagination (as        
the faculty of intuitions a priori) is undesignedly brought into            
accord with understanding (as the faculty of concepts), by means of         
a given representation, and a feeling of pleasure is thereby                
aroused, then the object must be regarded as final for the                  
reflective judgement. A judgement of this kind is an aesthetic              
judgement upon the finality of the object, which does not depend            
upon any present concept of the object, and does not provide one. When      
the form of an object (as opposed to the matter of its representation,      
as sensation) is, in the mere act of reflecting upon it, without            
regard to any concept to be obtained from it, estimated as the              
ground of a pleasure in the representation of such an object, then          
this pleasure is also judged to be combined necessarily with the            
representation of it, and so not merely for the subject apprehending        
this form, but for all in general who pass judgement. The object is         
then called beautiful; and the faculty of judging by means of such a        
pleasure (and so also with universal validity) is called taste. For         
since the ground of the pleasure is made to reside merely in the            
form of the object for reflection generally, consequently not in any        
sensation of the object, and without any reference, either, to any          
concept that might have something or other in view, it is with the          
conformity to law in the empirical employment of judgement generally        
(unity of imagination and understanding) in the subject, and with this      
alone, that the representation of the object in reflection, the             
conditions of which are universally valid a priori, accords. And, as        
this accordance of the object with the faculties of the subject is          
contingent, it gives rise to a representation of a finality on the          
part of the object in respect of the cognitive faculties of the             
subject.                                                                    
  Here, now, is a pleasure which-as is the case with all pleasure or        
displeasure that is not brought about through the agency of the             
concept of freedom (i.e., through the antecedent determination of           
the higher faculty of desire by means of pure reason)-no concepts           
could ever enable us to regard as necessarily connected with the            
representation of an object. It must always be only through reflective      
perception that it is cognized as conjoined with this                       
representation. As with all empirical judgements, it is, consequently,      
unable to announce objective necessity or lay claim to a priori             
validity. But, then, the judgement of taste in fact only lays claim,        
like every other empirical judgement, to be valid for every one,            
and, despite its inner contingency this is always possible. The only        
point that is strange or out of the way about it is that it is not          
an empirical concept, but a feeling of pleasure (and so not a               
concept at all), that is yet exacted from every one by the judgement        
of taste, just as if it were a predicate united to the cognition of         
the object, and that is meant to be conjoined with its representation.      
  A singular empirical judgement, as for example, the judgement of one      
who perceives a movable drop of water in a rock-crystal, rightly looks      
to every one finding the fact as stated, since the judgement has            
been formed according to the universal conditions of the determinant        
judgement under the laws of a possible experience generally. In the         
same way, one who feels pleasure in simple reflection on the form of        
an object, without having any concept in mind, rightly lays claim to        
the agreement of every one, although this judgement is empirical and a      
singular judgement. For the ground of this pleasure is found in the         
universal, though subjective, condition of reflective judgements,           
namely the final harmony of an object (be it a product of nature or of      
art) with the mutual relation of the faculties of cognition                 
(imagination and understanding), which are requisite for every              
empirical cognition. The pleasure in judgements of taste is,                
therefore, dependent doubtless on an empirical representation, and          
cannot be united a priori to any concept (one cannot determine a            
priori what object will be in accordance with taste or not-one must         
find out the object that is so); but then it is only made the               
determining ground of this judgement by virtue of our consciousness of      
its resting simply upon reflection and the universal, though only           
subjective, conditions of the harmony of that reflection with the           
knowledge of objects generally, for which the form of the object is         
final.                                                                      
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 70}
  This is why judgements of taste are subjected to a critique in            
respect of their possibility. For their possibility presupposes an a        
priori principle, although that principle is neither a cognitive            
principle for understanding nor a practical principle for the will,         
and is thus in no way determinant a priori.                                 
  Susceptibility to pleasure arising from reflection on the forms of        
things (whether of nature or of art) betokens, however, not only a          
finality on the part of objects in their relation to the reflective         
judgement in the subject, in accordance with the concept of nature,         
but also, conversely, a finality on the part of the subject, answering      
to the concept of freedom, in respect of the form, or even                  
formlessness of objects. The result is that the aesthetic judgement         
refers not merely, as a judgement of taste, to the beautiful, but           
also, as springing from a higher intellectual feeling, to the sublime.      
Hence the above-mentioned Critique of Aesthetic judgement must be           
divided on these lines into two main parts.                                 
-                                                                           
           VIII. The Logical Representation of the                          
                    Finality of Nature.                                     
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 75}
-                                                                           
  There are two ways in which finality may be represented in an object      
given in experience. It may be made to turn on what is purely               
subjective. In this case the object is considered in respect of its         
form as present in apprehension (apprehensio) prior to any concept;         
and the harmony of this form with the cognitive faculties, promoting        
the combination of the intuition with concepts for cognition                
generally, is represented as a finality of the form of the object. Or,      
on the other hand, the representation of finality may be made to            
turn on what is objective, in which case it is represented as the           
harmony of the form of the object with the possibility of the thing         
itself according to an antecedent concept of it containing the              
ground of this form. We have seen that the representation of the            
former kind of finality rests on the pleasure immediately felt in mere      
reflection on the form of the object. But that of the latter kind of        
finality, as it refers the form of the object, not to the subject's         
cognitive faculties engaged in its apprehension, but to a definite          
cognition of the object under a given concept, bas nothing to do            
with a feeling of pleasure in things, but only understanding and its        
estimate of them. Where the concept of an object is given, the              
function of judgement, in its employment of that concept for                
cognition, consists in presentation (exhibitio), i. e., in placing          
beside the concept an intuition corresponding to it. Here it may be         
that our own imagination is the agent employed, as in the case of art,      
where we realize a preconceived concept of an object which we set           
before ourselves as an end. Or the agent may be nature in its               
technic (as in the case of organic bodies), when we read into it our        
own concept of an end to assist our estimate of its product. In this        
case what is represented is not a mere finality of nature in the            
form of the thing, but this very product as a natural end. Although         
our concept that nature, in its empirical laws, is subjectively             
final in its forms is in no way a concept of the object, but only a         
principle of judgement for providing itself with concepts in the            
vast multiplicity of nature, so that it may be able to take its             
bearings, yet, on the analogy of an end, as it were a regard to our         
cognitive faculties is here attributed to nature. Natural beauty            
may, therefore, be looked on as the presentation of the concept of          
formal, i. e., merely subjective, finality and natural ends as the          
presentation of the concept of a real, i.e., objective, finality.           
The former of these we estimate by taste (aesthetically by means of         
the feeling of pleasure), the latter by understanding and reason            
(logically according to concepts).                                          
  On these considerations is based the division of the Critique of          
judgement into that of the aesthetic and the teleological judgement.        
By the first is meant the faculty of estimating formal finality             
(otherwise called subjective) by the feeling of pleasure or                 
displeasure, by the second, the faculty of estimating the real              
finality (objective) of nature by understanding and, reason.                
  In a Critique of judgement the part dealing with aesthetic judgement      
is essentially relevant, as it alone contains a principle introduced        
by judgement completely a priori as the basis of its reflection upon        
nature. This is the principle of nature's formal finality for our           
cognitive faculties in its particular (empirical) laws-a principle          
without which understanding could not feel itself at home in nature:        
whereas no reason is assignable a priori, nor is so much as the             
possibility of one apparent from the concept of nature as an object of      
experience, whether in its universal or in its particular aspects, why      
there should be objective ends of nature, i. e., things only                
possible as natural ends. But it is only judgement that, without being      
itself possessed a priori of a principle in that behalf, in actually        
occurring cases (of certain products) contains the rule for making use      
of the concept of ends in the interest of reason, after that the above      
transcendental principle has already prepared understanding to apply        
to nature the concept of an end (at least in respect of its form).          
  But the transcendental principle by which a finality of nature in         
its subjective reference to our cognitive faculties, is represented in      
the form of a thing as a principle of its estimation, leaves quite          
undetermined the question of where and in what cases we have to make        
our estimate of the object as a product according to a principle of         
finality, instead of simply according to universal laws of nature.          
It resigns to the aesthetic judgement the task of deciding the              
conformity of this product (in its form) to our cognitive faculties as      
a question of taste (a matter which the aesthetic judgement decides,        
not by any harmony with concepts, but by feeling). On the other             
hand, judgement as teleologically employed assigns the determinate          
conditions under which something (e. g., an organized body) is to be        
estimated after the idea of an end of nature. But it can adduce no          
principle from the concept of nature, as an object of experience, to        
give it its authority to ascribe a priori to nature a reference to          
ends, or even only indeterminately to assume them from actual               
experience in the case of such products. The reason of this is that,        
in order to be able merely empirically to cognize objective finality        
in a certain object, many particular experiences must be collected and      
reviewed under the unity of their principle. Aesthetic judgement is,        
therefore, a special faculty of estimating according to a rule, but         
not according to concepts. The teleological is not a special                
faculty, but only general reflective judgement proceeding, as it            
always does in theoretical cognition, according to concepts, but in         
respect of certain objects of nature, following special                     
principles-those, namely, of a judgement that is merely reflective and      
does not determine objects. Hence, as regards its application, it           
belongs to the theoretical part of philosophy, and on account of its        
special principles, which are not determinant, as principles belonging      
to doctrine have to be, it must also form a special part of the             
Critique. On the other hand, the aesthetic judgement contributes            
nothing to the cognition of its objects. Hence it must only be              
allocated to the Critique of the judging subject and of its                 
faculties of knowledge so far as these are capable of possessing a          
priori principles, be their use (theoretical or practical) otherwise        
what it may-a Critique which is the propaedeutic of all philosophy.         
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 80}
-                                                                           
       IX. Joinder of the Legislations of Understanding and                 
                 Reason by means of Judgement.                              
-                                                                           
  Understanding prescribes laws a priori for nature as an object of         
sense, so that we may have a theoretical knowledge of it in a possible      
experience. Reason prescribes laws a priori for freedom and its             
peculiar causality as the supersensible in the subject, so that we may      
have a purely practical knowledge. The realm of the concept of              
nature under the one legislation, and that of the concept of freedom        
under the other, are completely cut off from all reciprocal influence,      
that they might severally (each according to its own principles) exert      
upon the other, by the broad gulf that divides the supersensible            
from phenomena. The concept of freedom determines nothing in respect        
of the theoretical cognition of nature; and the concept of nature           
likewise nothing in respect of the practical laws of freedom. To            
that extent, then, it is not possible to throw a bridge from the one        
realm to the other. Yet although the determining grounds of                 
causality according to the concept of freedom (and the practical            
rule that this contains) have no place in nature, and the sensible          
cannot determine the supersensible in the subject; still the                
converse is possible (not, it is true, in respect of the knowledge          
of nature, but of the consequences arising from the supersensible           
and bearing on the sensible). So much indeed is implied in the concept      
of a causality by freedom, the operation of which, in conformity            
with the formal laws of freedom, is to take effect in the word. The         
word cause, however, in its application to the supersensible only           
signifies the ground that determines the causality of things of nature      
to an effect in conformity with their appropriate natural laws, but at      
the same time also in unison with the formal principle of the laws          
of reason-a ground which, while its possibility is impenetrable, may        
still be completely cleared of the charge of contradiction that it          
is alleged to involve.* The effect in accordance with the concept of        
freedom is the final end which (or the manifestation of which in the        
sensible world) is to exist, and this presupposes the condition of the      
possibility of that end in nature (i. e., in the nature of the subject      
as a being of the sensible world, namely, as man). It is so                 
presupposed a priori, and without regard to the practical, by               
judgement. This faculty, with its concept of a finality of nature,          
provides us with the mediating concept between concepts of nature           
and the concept of freedom-a concept that makes possible the                
transition from the pure theoretical [legislation of understanding] to      
the pure practical [legislation of reason] and from conformity to           
law in accordance with the former to final ends according to the            
latter. For through that concept we cognize the possibility of the          
final end that can only be actualized in nature and in harmony with         
its laws.                                                                   
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 85}
-                                                                           
  *One of the various supposed contradictions in this complete              
distinction of the causality of nature from that through freedom is         
expressed in the objection that when I speak of hindrances opposed          
by nature to causality according to laws of freedom (moral laws) or of      
assistance lent to it by nature, I am all the time admitting an             
influence of the former upon the latter. But the misinterpretation          
is easily avoided, if attention is only paid to the meaning of the          
statement. The resistance or furtherance is not between nature and          
freedom, but between the former as phenomenon and the effects of the        
latter as phenomena in the world of sense. Even the causality of            
freedom (of pure and practical reason) is the causality of a natural        
cause subordinated to freedom (a causality of the subject regarded          
as man, and consequently as a phenomenon), and one, the ground of           
whose determination is contained in the intelligible, that is               
thought under freedom, in a manner that is not further or otherwise         
explicable (just as in the case of that intelligible that forms the         
supersensible substrate of nature.)                                         
-                                                                           
  Understanding, by the possibility of its supplying a priori laws for      
nature, furnishes a proof of the fact that nature is cognized by us         
only as phenomenon, and in so doing points to its having a                  
supersensible substrate; but this substrate it leaves quite                 
undetermined. judgement by the a priori principle of its estimation of      
nature according to its possible particular laws provides this              
supersensible substrate (within as well as without us) with                 
determinability through the intellectual faculty. But reason gives          
determination to the same a priori by its practical law. Thus               
judgement makes possible the transition from the realm of the               
concept of nature to that of the concept of freedom.                        
  In respect of the faculties of the soul generally, regarded as            
higher faculties, i.e., as faculties containing an autonomy,                
understanding is the one that contains the constitutive a priori            
principles for the faculty of cognition (the theoretical knowledge          
of nature). The feeling pleasure and displeasure is provided for by         
the judgement in its independence from concepts and from sensations         
that refer to the determination of the faculty of desire and would          
thus be capable of being immediately practical. For the faculty of          
desire there is reason, which is practical without mediation of any         
pleasure of whatsoever origin, and which determines for it, as a            
higher faculty, the final end that is attended at the same time with        
pure intellectual delight in the object. judgement's concept of a           
finality of nature falls, besides, under the head of natural concepts,      
but only as a regulative principle of the cognitive faculties-although      
the aesthetic judgement on certain objects (of nature or of art) which      
occasions that concept, is a constitutive principle in respect of           
the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. The spontaneity in the play of      
the cognitive faculties whose harmonious accord contains the ground of      
this pleasure, makes the concept in question, in its consequences, a        
suitable mediating link connecting the realm of the concept of              
nature with that of the concept of freedom, as this accord at the same      
time promotes the sensibility of the mind for or moral feeling. The         
following table may facilitate the review of all the above faculties        
in their systematic unity.*                                                 
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 90}
-                                                                           
  *It has been thought somewhat suspicious that my divisions in pure        
philosophy should almost always come out threefold. But it is due to        
the nature of the case. If a division is to be a priori it must be          
either analytic, according to the law of contradiction-and then it          
is always twofold (quodlibet ens est aut A aut non A)-Or else it is         
synthetic. If it is to be derived in the latter case from a priori          
concepts (not, as in mathematics, from the a priori intuition               
corresponding to the concept), then, to meet the requirements of            
synthetic unity in general, namely (1) a condition, (2) a conditioned,      
(3) the concept arising from the union of the conditioned with its          
condition, the division must of necessity be trichotomous.                  
-                                                                           
     List of Mental Faculties      Cognitive Faculties                      
       Cognitive faculties             Understanding                        
                                                       {INTRO ^paragraph 95}
       Feeling of pleasure             Judgement                            
         and displeasure               Reason                               
       Faculty of desire                                                    
-                                                                           
      A priori Principles             Application                           
                                                      {INTRO ^paragraph 100}
       Conformity to law                 Nature                             
       Finality                          Art                                
       Final End                         Freedom                            
-                                                                           
                                                                            
SEC1|BK1                                                                    
           FIRST PART CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT                       
           SECTION I. ANALYTIC OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT.                      
               BOOK I. Analytic of the Beautiful.                           
-                                                                           
          FIRST MOMENT. Of the Judgement of Taste*:                         
                      Moment of Quality.                                    
-                                                                           
                                                     {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 5}
  *The definition of taste here relied upon is that it is the               
faculty of estimating the beautiful. But the discovery of what is           
required for calling an object beautiful must be reserved for the           
analysis of judgements of taste. In my search for the moments to which      
attention is paid by this judgement in its reflection, I have followed      
the guidance of the logical functions of judging (for a judgement of        
taste always involves a reference to understanding). I have brought         
the moment of quality first under review, because this is what the          
aesthetic judgement on the beautiful looks to in the first instance.        
-                                                                           
           SS 1. The judgement of taste is aesthetic.                       
-                                                                           
  If we wish to discern whether anything is beautiful or not, we do         
not refer the representation of it to the object by means of                
understanding with a view to cognition, but by means of the                 
imagination (acting perhaps in conjunction with understanding) we           
refer the representation to the subject and its feeling of pleasure or      
displeasure. The judgement of taste, therefore, is not a cognitive          
judgement, and so not logical, but is aesthetic-which means that it is      
one whose determining ground cannot be other than subjective. Every         
reference of representations is capable of being objective, even            
that of sensations (in which case it signifies the real in an               
empirical representation). The one exception to this is the feeling of      
pleasure or displeasure. This denotes nothing in the object, but is         
a feeling which the subject has of itself and of the manner in which        
it is affected by the representation.                                       
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 10}
  To apprehend a regular and appropriate building with one's cognitive      
faculties, be the mode of representation clear or confused, is quite a      
different thing from being conscious of this representation with an         
accompanying sensation of delight. Here the representation is referred      
wholly to the subject, and what is more to its feeling of life-under        
the name of the feeling of pleasure or displeasure-and this forms           
the basis of a quite separate faculty of discriminating and                 
estimating, that contributes nothing to knowledge. All it does is to        
compare the given representation in the subject with the entire             
faculty of representations of which the mind is conscious in the            
feeling of its state. Given representations in a judgement may be           
empirical, and so aesthetic; but the judgement which is pronounced          
by their means is logical, provided it refers them to the object.           
Conversely, be the given representations even rational, but referred        
in a judgement solely to the subject (to its feeling), they are always      
to that extent aesthetic.                                                   
-                                                                           
     SS 2. The delight which determines the judgement of                    
           taste is independent of all interest.                            
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 15}
  The delight which we connect with the representation of the real          
existence of an object is called interest. Such a delight,                  
therefore, always involves a reference to the faculty of desire,            
either as its determining ground, or else as necessarily implicated         
with its determining ground. Now, where the question is whether             
something is beautiful, we do not want to know, whether we, or any one      
else, are, or even could be, concerned in the real existence of the         
thing, but rather what estimate we form of it on mere contemplation         
(intuition or reflection). If any one asks me whether I consider            
that the palace I see before me is beautiful, I may, perhaps, reply         
that I do not care for things of that sort that are merely made to          
be gaped at. Or I may reply in the same strain as that Iroquois sachem      
who said that nothing in Paris pleased him better than the                  
eating-houses. I may even go a step further and inveigh with the            
vigour of a Rousseau against the vigour of a great against the              
vanity of the of the people on such superfluous things. Or, in fine, I      
may quite easily persuade myself that if I found myself on an               
uninhabited island, without hope of ever again coming among men, and        
could conjure such a palace into existence by a mere wish, I should         
still not trouble to do so, so long as I had a hut there that was           
comfortable enough for me. All this may be admitted and approved; only      
it is not the point now at issue. All one wants to know is whether the      
mere representation of the object is to my liking, no matter how            
indifferent I may be to the real existence of the object of this            
representation. It is quite plain that in order to say that the object      
is beautiful, and to show that I have taste, everything turns on the        
meaning which I can give to this representation, and not on any factor      
which makes me dependent on the real existence of the object. Every         
one must allow that a judgement on the beautiful which is tinged            
with the slightest interest, is very partial and not a pure                 
judgement of taste. One must not be in the least prepossessed in            
favour of the real existence of the thing, but must preserve                
complete indifference in this respect, in order to play the part of         
judge in matters of taste.                                                  
  This proposition, which is of the utmost importance, cannot be            
better explained than by contrasting the pure disinterested* delight        
which appears in the judgement of taste with that allied to an              
interest-especially if we can also assure ourselves that there are          
no other kinds of interest beyond those presently to be mentioned.          
-                                                                           
  *A judgement upon an object of our delight may be wholly                  
disinterested but withal very interesting, i.e., it relies on no            
interest, but it produces one. Of this kind are all pure moral              
judgements. But, of themselves judgements of taste do not even set          
up any interest whatsoever. Only in society is it interesting to            
have taste-a point which will be explained in the sequel.                   
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 20}
    SS 3. Delight in the agreeable is coupled with interest.                
-                                                                           
  That is agreeable which the senses find pleasing in sensation.            
This at once affords a convenient opportunity for condemning and            
directing particular attention to a prevalent confusion of the              
double meaning of which the word sensation is capable. All delight (as      
is said or thought) is itself sensation (of a pleasure).                    
Consequently everything that pleases, and for the very reason that          
it pleases, is agreeable-and according to its different degrees, or         
its relations to other agreeable sensations, is attractive,                 
charming, delicious, enjoyable, etc. But if this is conceded, then          
impressions of sense, which determine inclination, or principles of         
reason, which determine the will, or mere contemplated forms of             
intuition, which determine judgement, are all on a par in everything        
relevant to their effect upon the feeling of pleasure, for this             
would be agreeableness in the sensation of one's state; and since,          
in the last resort, all the elaborate work of our faculties must issue      
in and unite in the practical as its goal, we could credit our              
faculties with no other appreciation of things and the worth of             
things, than that consisting in the gratification which they                
promise. How this is attained is in the end immaterial; and, as the         
choice of the means is here the only thing that can make a difference,      
men might indeed blame one another for folly or imprudence, but             
never for baseness or wickedness; for they are all, each according          
to his own way of looking at things, pursuing one goal, which for each      
is the gratification in question.                                           
  When a modification of the feeling of pleasure or displeasure is          
termed sensation, this expression is given quite a different meaning        
to that which it bears when I call the representation of a thing            
(through sense as a receptivity pertaining to the faculty of                
knowledge) sensation. For in the latter case the representation is          
referred to the object, but in the former it is referred solely to the      
subject and is not available for any cognition, not even for that by        
which the subject cognizes itself.                                          
  Now in the above definition the word sensation is used to denote          
an objective representation of sense; and, to avoid continually             
running the risk of misinterpretation, we shall call that which must        
always remain purely subjective, and is absolutely incapable of             
forming a representation of an object, by the familiar name of              
feeling. The green colour of the meadows belongs to objective               
sensation, as the perception of an object of sense; but its                 
agreeableness to subjective sensation, by which no object is                
represented; i.e., to feeling, through which the object is regarded as      
an object of delight (which involves no cognition of the object).           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 25}
  Now, that a judgement on an object by which its agreeableness is          
affirmed, expresses an interest in it, is evident from the fact that        
through sensation it provokes a desire for similar objects,                 
consequently the delight presupposes, not the simple judgement about        
it, but the bearing its real existence has upon my state so far as          
affected by such an object. Hence we do not merely say of the               
agreeable that it pleases, but that it gratifies. I do not accord it a      
simple approval, but inclination is aroused by it, and where                
agreeableness is of the liveliest type a judgement on the character of      
the object is so entirely out of place that those who are always            
intent only on enjoyment (for that is the word used to denote               
intensity of gratification) would fain dispense with all judgement.         
-                                                                           
       SS 4. Delight in the good is coupled with interest.                  
-                                                                           
  That is good which by means of reason commends itself by its mere         
concept. We call that good for something which only pleases as a            
means; but that which pleases on its own account we call good in            
itself. In both cases the concept of an end is implied, and                 
consequently the relation of reason to (at least possible) willing,         
and thus a delight in the existence of an object or action, i.e., some      
interest or other.                                                          
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 30}
  To deem something good, I must always know what sort of a thing           
the object is intended to be, i. e., I must have a concept of it. That      
is not necessary to enable me to see beauty in a thing. Flowers,            
free patterns, lines aimlessly intertwining-technically termed              
foliage-have no signification, depend upon no definite concept, and         
yet please. Delight in the beautiful must depend upon the reflection        
on an object precursory to some (not definitely determined) concept.        
It is thus also differentiated from the agreeable, which rests              
entirely upon sensation.                                                    
  In many cases, no doubt, the agreeable and the good seem convertible      
terms. Thus it is commonly said that all (especially lasting)               
gratification is of itself good; which is almost equivalent to              
saying that to be permanently agreeable and to be good are                  
identical. But it is readily apparent that this is merely a vicious         
confusion of words, for the concepts appropriate to these                   
expressions are far from interchangeable. The agreeable, which, as          
such, represents the object solely in relation to sense, must in the        
first instance be brought under principles of reason through the            
concept of an end, to be, as an object of will, called good. But            
that the reference to delight is wholly different where what gratifies      
is at the same time called good, is evident from the fact that with         
the good the question always is whether it is mediately or immediately      
good, i. e., useful or good in itself; whereas with the agreeable this      
point can never arise, since the word always means what pleases             
immediately-and it is just the same with what I call beautiful.             
  Even in everyday parlance, a distinction is drawn between the             
agreeable and the good. We do not scruple to say of a dish that             
stimulates the palate with spices and other condiments that it is           
agreeable owning all the while that it is not good: because, while          
it immediately satisfies the senses, it is mediately displeasing, i.        
e., in the eye of reason that looks ahead to the consequences. Even in      
our estimate of health, this same distinction may be traced. To all         
that possess it, it is immediately agreeable-at least negatively, i.        
e., as remoteness of all bodily pains. But, if we are to say that it        
is good, we must further apply to reason to direct it to ends, that         
is, we must regard it as a state that puts us in a congenial mood           
for all we have to do. Finally, in respect of happiness every one           
believes that the greatest aggregate of the pleasures of life,              
taking duration as well as number into account, merits the name of a        
true, nay even of the highest, good. But reason sets its face               
against this too. Agreeableness is enjoyment. But if this is all            
that we are bent on, it would be foolish to be scrupulous about the         
means that procure it for us-whether it be obtained passively by the        
bounty of nature or actively and by the work of our own hands. But          
that there is any intrinsic worth in the real existence of a man who        
merely lives for enjoyment, however busy he may be in this respect,         
even when in so doing he serves others-all equally with himself intent      
only on enjoyment-as an excellent means to that one end, and does           
so, moreover, because through sympathy he shares all their                  
gratifications-this is a view to which reason will never let itself be      
brought round. Only by what a man does heedless of enjoyment, in            
complete freedom, and independently of what he can procure passively        
from the hand of nature, does be give to his existence, as the real         
existence of a person, an absolute worth. Happiness, with all its           
plethora of pleasures, is far from being an unconditioned good.*            
-                                                                           
  *An obligation to enjoyment is a patent absurdity. And the same,          
then, must also be said of a supposed obligation to actions that            
have merely enjoyment for their aim, no matter how spiritually this         
enjoyment may be refined in thought (or embellished), and even if it        
be a mystical, so-called heavenly, enjoyment.                               
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 35}
-                                                                           
  But, despite all this difference between the agreeable and the good,      
they both agree in being invariably coupled with an interest in             
their object. This is true, not alone of the agreeable, SS 3, and of        
the mediately good, i, e., the useful, which pleases as a means to          
some pleasure, but also of that which is good absolutely and from           
every point of view, namely the moral good which carries with it the        
highest interest. For the good is the object of will, i. e., of a           
rationally determined faculty of desire). But to will something, and        
to take a delight in its existence, i.e., to take an interest in it,        
are identical.                                                              
-                                                                           
      SS 5. Comparison of the three specifically different                  
                     kinds of delight.                                      
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 40}
-                                                                           
  Both the agreeable and the good involve a reference to the faculty        
of desire, and are thus attended, the former with a delight                 
pathologically conditioned (by stimuli), the latter with a pure             
practical delight. Such delight is determined not merely by the             
representation of the object, but also by the represented bond of           
connection between the subject and the real existence of the object.        
It is not merely the object, but also its real existence, that              
pleases. On the other hand, the judgement of taste is simply                
contemplative, i. e., it is a judgement which is indifferent as to the      
existence of an object, and only decides how its character stands with      
the feeling of pleasure and displeasure. But not even is this               
contemplation itself directed to concepts; for the judgement of             
taste is not a cognitive judgement (neither a theoretical one nor a         
practical), and hence, also, is not grounded on concepts, nor yet           
intentionally directed to them.                                             
  The agreeable, the beautiful, and the good thus denote three              
different relations of representations to the feeling of pleasure           
and displeasure, as a feeling in respect of which we distinguish            
different objects or modes of representation. Also, the                     
corresponding expressions which indicate our satisfaction in them           
are different The agreeable is what GRATIFIES a man; the beautiful          
what simply PLEASES him; the good what is ESTEEMED (approved), i.e.,        
that on which he sets an objective worth. Agreeableness is a                
significant factor even with irrational animals; beauty has purport         
and significance only for human beings, i.e., for beings at once            
animal and rational (but not merely for them as rational-intelligent        
beings-but only for them as at once animal and rational); whereas           
the good is good for every rational being in general-a proposition          
which can only receive its complete justification and explanation in        
the sequel. Of all these three kinds of delight, that of taste in           
the beautiful may be said to be the one and only disinterested and          
free delight; for, with it, no interest, whether of sense or reason,        
extorts approval. And so we may say that delight, in the three cases        
mentioned, is related to inclination, to favour, or to respect. For         
FAVOUR is the only free liking. An object of inclination, and one           
which a law of reason imposes upon our desire, leaves us no freedom to      
turn anything into an object of pleasure. All interest presupposes a        
want, or calls one forth; and, being a ground determining approval,         
deprives the judgement on the object of its freedom.                        
  So far as the interest of inclination in the case of the agreeable        
goes, every one says "Hunger is the best sauce; and people with a           
healthy appetite relish everything, so long as it is something they         
can eat." Such delight, consequently, gives no indication of taste          
having anything to say to the choice. Only when men have got all            
they want can we tell who among the crowd has taste or not.                 
Similarly there may be correct habits (conduct) without virtue,             
politeness without good-will, propriety without honour, etc. For where      
the moral law dictates, there is, objectively, no room left for free        
choice as to what one has to do; and to show taste in the way one           
carries out these dictates, or in estimating the way others do so,          
is a totally different matter from displaying the moral frame of one's      
mind. For the latter involves a command and produces a need of              
something, whereas moral taste only plays with the objects of               
delight without devoting itself sincerely to any.                           
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 45}
  Definition of the Beautiful derived from the First Moment.                
-                                                                           
  Taste is the faculty of estimating an object or a mode of                 
representation by means of a delight or aversion apart from any             
interest. The object of such a delight is called beautiful.                 
-                                                                           
           SECOND MOMENT. Of the Judgement of Taste:                        
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 50}
                     Moment of Quantity.                                    
-                                                                           
        SS 6. The beautiful is that which, apart from                       
            concepts, is represented as the Object                          
                  of a universal delight.                                   
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 55}
-                                                                           
  This definition of the beautiful is deducible from the foregoing          
definition of it as an object of delight apart from any interest.           
For where any one is conscious that his delight in an object is with        
him independent of interest, it is inevitable that he should look on        
the object as one containing a ground of delight for all men. For,          
since the delight is not based on any inclination of the subject (or        
on any other deliberate interest), but the subject feels himself            
completely free in respect of the liking which he accords to the            
object, he can find as reason for his delight no personal conditions        
to which his own subjective self might alone be party. Hence he must        
regard it as resting on what he may also presuppose in every other          
person; and therefore he must believe that he has reason for demanding      
a similar delight from every one. Accordingly he will speak of the          
beautiful as if beauty were a quality of the object and the                 
judgement logical (forming a cognition of the object by concepts of         
it); although it is only aesthetic, and contains merely a reference of      
the representation of the object to the subject; because it still           
bears this resemblance to the logical judgement, that it may be             
presupposed to be valid for all men. But this universality cannot           
spring from concepts. For from concepts there is no transition to           
the feeling of pleasure or displeasure (save in the case of pure            
practical laws, which, however, carry an interest with them; and            
such an interest does not attach to the pure judgement of taste).           
The result is that the judgement of taste, with its attendant               
consciousness of detachment from all interest, must involve a claim to      
validity for all men, and must do so apart from universality                
attached to objects, i.e., there must be coupled with it a claim to         
subjective universality.                                                    
-                                                                           
      SS 7. Comparison of the beautiful with the agreeable                  
       and the good by means of the above characteristic.                   
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 60}
-                                                                           
  As regards the agreeable, every one concedes that his judgement,          
which he bases on a private feeling, and in which he declares that          
an object pleases him, is restricted merely to himself personally.          
Thus he does not take it amiss if, when he says that Canary-wine is         
agreeable, another corrects the expression and reminds him that he          
ought to say: "It is agreeable to me." This applies not only to the         
taste of the tongue, the palate, and the throat, but to what may            
with any one be agreeable to eye or ear. A violet colour is to one          
soft and lovely: to another dull and faded. One man likes the tone          
of wind instruments, another prefers that of string instruments. To         
quarrel over such points with the idea of condemning another's              
judgement as incorrect when it differs from our own, as if the              
opposition between the two judgements were logical, would be folly.         
With the agreeable, therefore, the axiom holds good: Every one has his      
own taste (that of sense).                                                  
  The beautiful stands on quite a different footing. It would, on           
the contrary, be ridiculous if any one who plumed himself on his taste      
were to think of justifying himself by saying: "This object (the            
building we see, the dress that person has on, the concert we hear,         
the poem submitted to our criticism) is beautiful for me." For if it        
merely pleases him, be must not call it beautiful. Many things may for      
him possess charm and agreeableness-no one cares about that; but            
when he puts a thing on a pedestal and calls it beautiful, he               
demands the same delight from others. He judges not merely for              
himself, but for all men, and then speaks of beauty as if it were a         
property of things. Thus he says the thing is beautiful; and it is not      
as if he counted on others agreeing in his judgement of liking owing        
to his having found them in such agreement on a number of occasions,        
but he demands this agreement of them. He blames them if they judge         
differently, and denies them taste, which he still requires of them as      
something they ought to have; and to this extent it is not open to men      
to say: "Every one has his own taste." This would be equivalent to          
saying that there is no such thing at all as taste, i. e., no               
aesthetic judgement capable of making a rightful claim upon the assent      
of all men.                                                                 
  Yet even in the case of the agreeable, we find that the estimates         
men form do betray a prevalent agreement among them, which leads to         
our crediting some with taste and denying it to others, and that, too,      
not as an organic sense but as a critical faculty in respect of the         
agreeable generally. So of one who knows how to entertain his guests        
with pleasures (of enjoyment through all the senses) in such a way          
that one and all are pleased, we say that he has taste. But the             
universality here is only understood in a comparative sense; and the        
rules that apply are, like all empirical rules, general only, not           
universal, the latter being what the judgement of taste upon the            
beautiful deals or claims to deal in. It is a judgement in respect          
of sociability so far as resting on empirical rules. In respect of the      
good, it is true that judgements also rightly assert a claim to             
validity for every one; but the good is only represented as an              
object of universal delight by means of a concept, which is the case        
neither with the agreeable nor the beautiful.                               
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 65}
       SS 8. In a judgement of taste the universality of                    
          delight is only represented as subjective.                        
-                                                                           
  This particular form of the universality of an aesthetic                  
judgement, which is to be met in a judgement of taste, is a                 
significant feature, not for the logician certainly, but for the            
transcendental philosopher. It calls for no small effort on his part        
to discover its origin, but in return it brings to light a property of      
our cognitive faculty which, without this analysis, would have              
remained unknown.                                                           
  First, one must get firmly into one's mind that by the judgement          
of taste (upon the beautiful) the delight in an object is imputed to        
every one, yet without being founded on a concept (for then it would        
be the good), and that this claim to universality is such an essential      
factor of a judgement by which we describe anything as beautiful, that      
were it not for its being present to the mind it would never enter          
into any one's head to use this expression, but everything that             
pleased without a concept would be ranked as agreeable. For in respect      
of the agreeable, every one is allowed to have his own opinion, and no      
one insists upon others agreeing with his judgement of taste, which is      
what is invariably done in the judgement of taste about beauty. The         
first of these I may call the taste of sense, the second, the taste of      
reflection: the first laying down judgements merely private, the            
second, on the other hand, judgements ostensibly of general validity        
(public), but both alike being aesthetic (not practical) judgements         
about an object merely in respect of the bearings of its                    
representation on the feeling of pleasure or displeasure. Now it            
does seem strange that while with the taste of sense it is not alone        
experience that shows that its judgement (of pleasure or displeasure        
in something) is not universally valid, but every one willingly             
refrains from imputing this agreement to others (despite the                
frequent actual prevalence of a considerable consensus of general           
opinion even in these judgements), the taste of reflection, which,          
as experience teaches, has often enough to put up with a rude               
dismissal of its claims to universal validity of its judgement (upon        
the beautiful), can (as it actually does) find it possible for all          
that to formulate judgements capable of demanding this agreement in         
its universality. Such agreement it does in fact require from every         
one for each of its judgements of taste the persons who pass these          
judgements not quarreling over the possibility of such a claim, but         
only failing in particular cases to come to terms as to the correct         
application of this faculty.                                                
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 70}
  First of all we have here to note that a universality which does not      
rest upon concepts of the object (even though these are only                
empirical) is in no way logical, but aesthetic, i. e., does not             
involve any objective quantity of the judgement, but only one that          
is subjective. For this universality I use the expression general           
validity, which denotes the validity of the reference of a                  
representation, not to the cognitive faculties, but to the feeling          
of pleasure or displeasure for every subject. (The same expression,         
however, may also be employed for the logical quantity of the               
judgement, provided we add objective universal validity, to                 
distinguish it from the merely subjective validity which is always          
aesthetic.)                                                                 
  Now a judgement that has objective universal validity has always got      
the subjective also, i.e., if the judgement is valid for everything         
which is contained under a given concept, it is valid also for all who      
represent an object by means of this concept. But from a subjective         
universal validity, i. e., the aesthetic, that does not rest on any         
concept, no conclusion can be drawn to the logical; because judgements      
of that kind have no bearing upon the object. But for this very reason      
the aesthetic universality attributed to a judgement must also be of a      
special kind, seeing that it does not join the predicate of beauty          
to the concept of the object taken in its entire logical sphere, and        
yet does extend this predicate over the whole sphere of judging             
subjects.                                                                   
  In their logical quantity, all judgements of taste are singular           
judgements. For, since I must present the object immediately to my          
feeling of pleasure or displeasure, and that, too, without the aid          
of concepts, such judgements cannot have the quantity of judgements         
with objective general validity. Yet by taking the singular                 
representation of the object of the judgement of taste, and by              
comparison converting it into a concept according to the conditions         
determining that judgement, we can arrive at a logically universal          
judgement. For instance, by a judgement of the taste I describe the         
rose at which I am looking as beautiful. The judgement, on the other        
hand, resulting from the comparison of a number of singular                 
representations: "Roses in general are beautiful," is no longer             
pronounced as a purely aesthetic judgement, but as a logical judgement      
founded on one that is aesthetic. Now the judgement, "The rose is           
agreeable" (to smell) is also, no doubt, an aesthetic and singular          
judgement, but then it is not one of taste but of sense. For it has         
this point of difference from a judgement of taste, that the latter         
imports an aesthetic quantity of universality, i.e., of validity for        
everyone which is not to be met with in a judgement upon the                
agreeable. It is only judgements upon the good which, while also            
determining the delight in an object, possess logical and not mere          
aesthetic universality; for it is as involving a cognition of the           
object that "they are valid of it, and on that account valid for            
everyone.                                                                   
  In forming an estimate of objects merely from concepts, all               
representation of beauty goes by the board. There can, therefore, be        
no rule according to which any one is to be compelled to recognize          
anything as beautiful. Whether a dress, a house, or a flower is             
beautiful is a matter upon which one declines to allow one's judgement      
to be swayed by any reasons or principles. We want to get a look at         
the object with our own eyes, just as if our delight depended on            
sensation. And yet, if upon so doing, we call the object beautiful, we      
believe ourselves to be speaking with a universal voice, and lay claim      
to the concurrence of everyone, whereas no private sensation would          
be decisive except for the observer alone and his liking.                   
   Here, now, we may perceive that nothing is postulated in the             
judgement of taste but such a universal voice in respect of delight         
that it is not mediated by concepts; consequently, only the                 
possibility of an aesthetic judgement capable of being at the same          
time deemed valid for everyone. The judgement of taste itself does not      
postulate the agreement of everyone (for it is only competent for a         
logically universal judgement to do this, in that it is able to             
bring forward reasons); it only imputes this agreement to everyone, as      
an instance of the rule in respect of which it looks for confirmation,      
not from concepts, but from the concurrence of others. The universal        
voice is, therefore, only an idea -resting upon grounds the                 
investigation of which is here postponed. It may be a matter of             
uncertainty whether a person who thinks he is laying down a                 
judgement of taste is, in fact, judging in conformity with that             
idea; but that this idea is what is contemplated in his judgement, and      
that, consequently, it is meant to be a judgement of taste, is              
proclaimed by his use of the expression "beauty." For himself he can        
be certain on the point from his mere consciousness of the                  
separation of everything belonging to the agreeable and the good            
from the delight remaining to him; and this is all for which be             
promises himself the agreement of everyone-a claim which, under             
these conditions, he would also be warranted in making, were it not         
that he frequently sinned against them, and thus passed an erroneous        
judgement of taste.                                                         
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 75}
-                                                                           
     SS 9. Investigation of the question of the relative                    
      priority in a judgement of taste of the feeling                       
       of pleasure and the estimating of the object.                        
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 80}
  The solution of this problem is the key to the Critique of taste,         
and so is worthy of all attention.                                          
  Were the pleasure in a given object to be the antecedent, and were        
the universal communicability of this pleasure to be all that the           
judgement of taste is meant to allow to the representation of the           
object, such a sequence would be self-contradictory. For a pleasure of      
that kind would be nothing but the feeling of mere agreeableness to         
the senses, and so, from its very nature, would possess no more than        
private validity, seeing that it would be immediately dependent on the      
representation through which the object is given.                           
  Hence it is the universal capacity for being communicated incident        
to the mental state in the given representation which, as the               
subjective condition of the judgement of taste, must be,                    
fundamental, with the pleasure in the object as its consequent.             
Nothing, however, is capable of being universally communicated but          
cognition and representation so far as appurtenant to cognition. For        
it is only as thus appurtenant that the representation is objective,        
and it is this alone that gives it a universal point of reference with      
which the power of representation of every one is obliged to                
harmonize. If, then, the determining ground of the judgement as to          
this universal communicability of the representation is to be merely        
subjective, that is to say, to be conceived independently of any            
concept of the object, it can be nothing else than the mental state         
that presents itself in the mutual relation of the powers of                
representation so far as they refer a given representation to               
cognition in general.                                                       
  The cognitive powers brought into play by this representation are         
here engaged in a free play, since no definite concept restricts            
them to a particular rule of cognition. Hence the mental state in this      
representation must be one of a feeling of the free play of the powers      
of representation in a given representation for a cognition in              
general. Now a representation, whereby an object is given, involves,        
in order that it may become a source of cognition at all,                   
imagination for bringing together the manifold of intuition, and            
understanding for the unity of the concept uniting the                      
representations. This state of free play of the cognitive faculties         
attending a representation by which an object is given must admit of        
universal communication: because cognition, as a definition of the          
object with which given representations (in any subject whatever)           
are to accord, is the one and only representation which is valid for        
everyone.                                                                   
  As the subjective universal communicability of the mode of                
representation in a judgement of taste is to subsist apart from the         
presupposition of any definite concept, it can be nothing else than         
the mental state present in the free play of imagination and                
understanding (so far as these are in mutual accord, as is requisite        
for cognition in general); for we are conscious that this subjective        
relation suitable for a cognition in general must be just as valid for      
every one, and consequently as universally communicable, as is any          
indeterminate cognition, which always rests upon that relation as           
its subjective condition.                                                   
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 85}
  Now this purely subjective (aesthetic) estimating of the object,          
or of the representation through which it is given, is antecedent to        
the pleasure in it, and is the basis of this pleasure in the harmony        
of the cognitive faculties. Again, the above-described universality of      
the subjective conditions of estimating objects forms the sole              
foundation of this universal subjective validity of the delight             
which we connect with the representation of the object that we call         
beautiful.                                                                  
  That an ability to communicate one's mental state, even though it be      
only in respect of our cognitive faculties, is attended with a              
pleasure, is a fact which might easily be demonstrated from the             
natural propensity of mankind to social life, i.e., empirically and         
psychologically. But what we have here in view calls for something          
more than this. In a judgement of taste, the pleasure felt by us is         
exacted from every one else as necessary, just as if, when we call          
something beautiful, beauty was to be regarded as a quality of the          
object forming part of its inherent determination according to              
concepts; although beauty is for itself, apart from any reference to        
the feeling of the subject, nothing. But the discussion of this             
question must be reserved until we have answered the further one of         
whether, and how, aesthetic judgements are possible a priori.               
  At present we are exercised with the lesser question of the way in        
which we become conscious, in a judgement of taste, of a reciprocal         
subjective common accord of the powers of cognition. Is it                  
aesthetically by sensation and our mere internal sense? Or is it            
intellectually by consciousness of our intentional activity in              
bringing these powers into play?                                            
  Now if the given representation occasioning the judgement of taste        
were a concept which united understanding and imagination in the            
estimate of the object so as to give a cognition of the object, the         
consciousness of this relation would be intellectual (as in the             
objective schematism of judgement dealt with in the Critique). But,         
then, in that case the judgement would not be laid down with respect        
to pleasure and displeasure, and so would not be a judgement of taste.      
But, now, the judgement of taste determines the object,                     
independently of concepts, in respect of delight and of the                 
predicate of beauty. There is, therefore, no other way for the              
subjective unity of the relation in question to make itself known than      
by sensation. The quickening of both faculties (imagination and             
understanding) to an indefinite, but yet, thanks to the given               
representation, harmonious activity, such as belongs to cognition           
generally, is the sensation whose universal communicability is              
postulated by the judgement of taste. An objective relation can, of         
course, only be thought, yet in so far as, in respect of its                
conditions, it is subjective, it may be felt in its effect upon the         
mind, and, in the case of a relation (like that of the powers of            
representation to a faculty of cognition generally) which does not          
rest on any concept, no other consciousness of it is possible beyond        
that through sensation of its effect upon the mind -an effect               
consisting in the more facile play of both mental powers                    
(imagination and understanding) as quickened by their mutual accord. A      
representation which is singular and independent of comparison with         
other representations, and, being such, yet accords with the                
conditions of the universality that is the general concern of               
understanding, is one that brings the cognitive faculties into that         
proportionate accord which we require for all cognition and which we        
therefore deem valid for every one who is so constituted as to judge        
by means of understanding and sense conjointly (i.e., for every man).       
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 90}
     Definition of the Beautiful drawn from the Second Moment.              
-                                                                           
  The beautiful is that which, apart from a concept, pleases                
universally.                                                                
-                                                                           
        THIRD MOMENT. Of Judgements of Taste: Moment of                     
                                                    {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 95}
         the relation of the Ends brought under Review                      
                     in such Judgements.                                    
-                                                                           
                 SS 10. Finality in general.                                
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 100}
  Let us define the meaning of "an end" in transcendental terms (i.e.,      
without presupposing anything empirical, such as the feeling of             
pleasure). An end is the object of a concept so far as this concept is      
regarded as the cause of the object (the real ground of its                 
possibility); and the causality of a concept in respect of its              
object is finality (forma finalis). Where, then, not the cognition          
of an object merely, but the object itself (its form or real                
existence) as an effect, is thought to be possible only through a           
concept of it, there we imagine an end. The representation of the           
effect is here the determining ground of its cause and takes the            
lead of it. The consciousness of the causality of a representation          
in respect of the state of the subject as one tending to preserve a         
continuance of that state, may here be said to denote in a general way      
what is called pleasure; whereas displeasure is that representation         
which contains the ground for converting the state of the                   
representations into their opposite (for hindering or removing them).       
  The faculty of desire, so far as determinable only through concepts,      
i.e., so as to act in conformity with the representation of an end,         
would be the Will. But an object, or state of mind, or even an              
action may, although its possibility does not necessarily presuppose        
the representation of an end, be called final simply on account of its      
possibility being only explicable and intelligible for us by virtue of      
an assumption on our part of fundamental causality according to             
ends, i.e., a will that would have so ordained it according to a            
certain represented rule. Finality, therefore, may exist apart from an      
end, in so far as we do not locate the causes of this form in a             
will, but yet are able to render the explanation of its possibility         
intelligible to ourselves only by deriving it from a will. Now we           
are not always obliged to look with the eye of reason into what we          
observe (i.e., to consider it in its possibility). So we may at             
least observe a finality of form, and trace it in objects-though by         
reflection only-without resting it on an end (as the material of the        
nexus finalis).                                                             
-                                                                           
     SS 11. The sole foundation of the judgement of taste                   
       is the form of finality of an object (or mode of                     
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 105}
                     representing it).                                      
-                                                                           
  Whenever an end is regarded as a source of delight, it always             
imports an interest as determining ground of the judgement on the           
object of pleasure. Hence the judgement of taste cannot rest on any         
subjective end as its ground. But neither can any representation of an      
objective end, i.e., of the possibility of the object itself on             
principles of final connection, determine the judgement of taste, and,      
consequently, neither can any concept of the good. For the judgement        
of taste is an aesthetic and not a cognitive judgement, and so does         
not deal with any concept of the nature or of the internal or external      
possibility, by this or that cause, of the object, but simply with the      
relative bearing of the representative powers so far as determined          
by a representation.                                                        
  Now this relation, present when an object is characterized as             
beautiful, is coupled with the feeling of pleasure. This pleasure is        
by the judgement of taste pronounced valid for every one; hence an          
agreeableness attending the representation is just as incapable of          
containing the determining ground of the judgement as the                   
representation of the perfection of the object or the concept of the        
good. We are thus left with the subjective finality in the                  
representation of an object, exclusive of any end (objective or             
subjective)-consequently the bare form of finality in the                   
representation whereby an object is given to us, so far as we are           
conscious of it as that which is alone capable of constituting the          
delight which, apart from any concept, we estimate as universally           
communicable, and so of forming the determining ground of the               
judgement of taste.                                                         
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 110}
         SS 12. The judgement of taste rests upon a                         
                      priori grounds.                                       
-                                                                           
  To determine a priori the connection of the feeling of pleasure or        
displeasure as an effect, with some representation or other (sensation      
or concept) as its cause, is utterly impossible; for that would be a        
causal relation which (with objects of experience) is always one            
that can only be cognized a posteriori and with the help of                 
experience. True, in the Critique of Practical Reason we did                
actually derive a priori from universal moral concepts the feeling          
of respect (as a particular and peculiar modification of this               
feeling which does not strictly answer either to the pleasure or            
displeasure which we receive from empirical objects). But there we          
were further able to cross the border of experience and call in aid         
a causality resting on a supersensible attribute of the subject,            
namely that of freedom. But even there it was not this feeling exactly      
that we deduced from the idea of the moral as cause, but from this was      
derived simply the determination of the will. But the mental state          
present in the determination of the will by any means is at once in         
itself a feeling of pleasure and identical with it, and so does not         
issue from it as an effect. Such an effect must only be assumed             
where the concept of the moral as a good precedes the determination of      
the will by the law; for in that case it would be futile to derive the      
pleasure combined with the concept from this concept as a mere              
cognition.                                                                  
  Now the pleasure in aesthetic judgements stands on a similar              
footing: only that here it is merely contemplative and does not             
bring about an interest in the object; whereas in the moral                 
judgement it is practical, The consciousness of mere formal finality        
in the play of the cognitive faculties of the subject attending a           
representation whereby an object is given, is the pleasure itself,          
because it involves a determining ground of the subject's activity          
in respect of the quickening of its cognitive powers, and thus an           
internal causality (which is final) in respect of cognition generally,      
but without being limited to a definite cognition, and consequently         
a mere form of the subjective finality of a representation in an            
aesthetic judgement. This pleasure is also in no way practical,             
neither resembling that form the pathological ground of                     
agreeableness nor that from the intellectual ground of the represented      
good. But still it involves an inherent causality, that, namely, of         
preserving a continuance of the state of the representation itself and      
the active engagement of the cognitive powers without ulterior aim. We      
dwell on the contemplation of the beautiful because this contemplation      
strengthens and reproduces itself. The case is analogous (but               
analogous only) to the way we linger on a charm in the                      
representation of an object which keeps arresting the attention, the        
mind all the while remaining passive.                                       
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 115}
-                                                                           
      SS 13. The pure judgement of taste is independent                     
                   of charm and emotion.                                    
-                                                                           
  Every interest vitiates the judgement of taste and robs it of its         
impartiality. This is especially so where, instead of, like the             
interest of reason, making finality take the lead of the lead of the        
feeling of pleasure, it grounds it upon this feeling-which is what          
always happens in aesthetic judgements upon anything so far as it           
gratifies or pains. Hence judgements so influenced can either lay no        
claim at all to a universally valid delight, or else must abate             
their claim in proportion as sensations of the kind in question             
enter into the determining grounds of taste. Taste that requires an         
added element of charm and emotion for its delight, not to speak of         
adopting this as the measure of its approval, has not yet emerged from      
barbarism.                                                                  
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 120}
  And yet charms are frequently not alone ranked with beauty (which         
ought properly to be a question merely of the form) as supplementary        
to the aesthetic universal delight, but they have been accredited as        
intrinsic beauties, and consequently the matter of delight passed           
off for the form. This is a misconception which, like many others that      
have still an underlying element of truth, may be removed by a careful      
definition of these concepts.                                               
  A judgement of taste which is uninfluenced by charm or emotion            
(though these may be associated with the delight in the beautiful),         
and whose determining ground, therefore, is simply finality of form,        
is a pure judgement of taste.                                               
-                                                                           
                    SS 14 Exemplification.                                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 125}
  Aesthetic, just like theoretical (logical) judgements, are divisible      
into empirical and pure. The first are those by which agreeableness or      
disagreeableness, the second those by which beauty is predicated of an      
object or its mode of representation. The former are judgements of          
sense (material aesthetic judgements), the latter (as formal) alone         
judgements of taste proper.                                                 
  A judgement of taste, therefore, is only pure so far as its               
determining ground is tainted with no merely empirical delight. But         
such a taint is always present where charm or emotion have a share          
in the judgement by which something is to be described as beautiful.        
  Here now there is a recrudescence of a number of specious pleas that      
go the length of putting forward the case that charm is not merely a        
necessary ingredient of beauty, but is even of itself sufficient to         
merit the name of beautiful. A mere colour, such as the green of a          
plot of grass, or a mere tone (as distinguished from sound or               
noise), like that of a violin, is described by most people as in            
itself beautiful, notwithstanding the fact that both seem to depend         
merely on the matter of the representations in other words, simply          
on sensation-which only entitles them to be called agreeable. But it        
will at the same time be observed that sensations of colour as well as      
of tone are only entitled to be immediately regarded as beautiful           
where, in either case, they are pure. This is a determination which at      
once goes to their form, and it is the only one which these                 
representations possess that admits with certainty of being                 
universally communicated. For it is not to be assumed that even the         
quality of the sensations agrees in all subjects, and we can hardly         
take it for granted that the agreeableness of a colour, or of the tone      
of a musical instrument, which we judge to be preferable to that of         
another, is given a like preference in the estimate of every one.           
  Assuming vibrations vibration sound, and, what is most important,         
that the mind not alone perceives by sense their effect in stimulating      
the organs, but also, by reflection, the regular play of the                
impressions (and consequently the form in which different                   
representations are united)-which I, still, in no way doubt-then            
colour and tone would not be mere sensations. They would be nothing         
short of formal determinations of the unity of a manifold of                
sensations, and in that case could even be ranked as intrinsic              
beauties.                                                                   
  But the purity of a simple mode of sensation means that its               
uniformity is not disturbed or broken by any foreign sensation. It          
belongs merely to the form; for abstraction may there be made from the      
quality of the mode of such sensation (what colour or tone, if any, it      
represents). For this reason, all simple colours are regarded as            
beautiful so far as pure. Composite colours have not this advantage,        
because, not being simple, there is no standard for estimating whether      
they should be called pure or impure.                                       
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 130}
  But as for the beauty ascribed to the object on account of its form,      
and the supposition that it is capable of being enhanced by charm,          
this is a common error and one very prejudicial to genuine,                 
uncorrupted, sincere taste. Nevertheless charms may be added to beauty      
to lend to the mind, beyond a bare delight, an adventitious interest        
in the representation of the object, and thus to advocate taste and         
its cultivation. This applies especially where taste is as yet crude        
and untrained. But they are positively subversive of the judgement          
of taste, if allowed to obtrude themselves as grounds of estimating         
beauty. For so far are they from contributing to beauty that it is          
only where taste is still weak and untrained that, like aliens, they        
are admitted as a favour, and only on terms that they do not violate        
that beautiful form.                                                        
  In painting, sculpture, and in fact in all the formative arts, in         
architecture and horticulture, so far as fine arts, the design is what      
is essential. Here it is not what gratifies in sensation but merely         
what pleases by its form, that is the fundamental prerequisite for          
taste. The colours which give brilliancy to the sketch are part of the      
charm. They may no doubt, in their own way, enliven the object for          
sensation, but make it really worth looking at and beautiful they           
cannot. Indeed, more often than not the requirements of the                 
beautiful form restrict them to a very narrow compass, and, even where      
charm is admitted, it is only this form that gives them a place of          
honour.                                                                     
  All form of objects of sense (both of external and also,                  
mediately, of internal sense) is either figure or play. In the              
latter case it is either play of figures (in space: mimic and               
dance), or mere play of sensations (in time). The charm of colours, or      
of the agreeable tones of instruments, may be added: but the design in      
the former and the composition in the latter constitute the proper          
object of the pure judgement of taste. To say that the purity alike of      
colours and of tones, or their variety and contrast, seem to                
contribute to beauty, is by no means to imply that, because in              
themselves agreeable, they therefore yield an addition to the               
delight in the form and one on a par with it. The real meaning              
rather is that they make this form more clearly, definitely, and            
completely intuitable, and besides stimulate the representation by          
their charm, as they excite and sustain the attention directed to           
the object itself.                                                          
  Even what is called ornamentation (parerga), i.e., what is only an        
adjunct and not an intrinsic constituent in the complete                    
representation of the object, in augmenting the delight of taste            
does so only by means of its form. Thus it is with the frames of            
pictures or the drapery on statues, or the colonnades of palaces.           
But if the ornamentation does not itself enter into the composition of      
the beautiful form-if it is introduced like a gold frame merely to win      
approval for the picture by means of its charm-it is then called            
finery and takes away from the genuine beauty.                              
  Emotion-a sensation where an agreeable feeling is produced merely by      
means of a momentary check followed by a more powerful outpouring of        
the vital force-is quite foreign to beauty. Sublimity (with which           
the feeling of emotion is connected) requires, however, a different         
standard of estimation from that relied upon by taste. A pure               
judgement of taste has, then, for its determining ground neither charm      
nor emotion, in a word, no sensation as matter of the aesthetic             
judgement.                                                                  
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 135}
-                                                                           
       SS 15. The judgement of taste is entirely independent                
                 of the concept of perfection.                              
-                                                                           
  Objective finality can only be cognized by means of a reference of        
the manifold to a definite end, and hence only through a concept. This      
alone makes it clear that the beautiful, which is estimated on the          
ground of a mere formal finality, i.e., a finality apart from an            
end, is wholly independent of the representation of the good. For           
the latter presupposes an objective finality, i.e., the reference of        
the object to a definite end.                                               
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 140}
  Objective finality is either external, i.e., the utility, or              
internal, i. e., the perfection, of the object. That the delight in an      
object on account of which we call it beautiful is incapable of             
resting on the representation of its utility, is abundantly evident         
from the two preceding articles; for in that case, it would not be          
an immediate delight in the object, which latter is the essential           
condition of the judgement upon beauty. But in an objective,                
internal finality, i.e., perfection, we have what is more akin to           
the predicate of beauty, and so this has been held even by                  
philosophers of reputation to be convertible with beauty, though            
subject to the qualification: where it is thought in a confused way.        
In a critique of taste it is of the utmost importance to decide             
whether beauty is really reducible to the concept of perfection.            
  For estimating objective finality we always require the concept of        
an end, and, where such finality has to be, not an external one             
(utility), but an internal one, the concept of an internal end              
containing the ground of the internal possibility of the object. Now        
an end is in general that, the concept of which may be regarded as the      
ground of the possibility of the object itself. So in order to              
represent an objective finality in a thing we must first have a             
concept of what sort of a thing it is to be. The agreement of the           
manifold in a thing with this concept (which supplies the rule of           
its synthesis) is the qualitative perfection of the thing.                  
Quantitative perfection is entirely distinct from this. It consists in      
the completeness of anything after its kind, and is a mere concept          
of quantity (of totality). In its case the question of what the             
thing is to be is regarded as definitely disposed of, and we only           
ask whether it is possessed of all the requisites that go to make it        
such. What is formal in the representation of a thing, i.e., the            
agreement of its manifold with a unity (i.e., irrespective of what          
it is to be), does not, of itself, afford us any cognition                  
whatsoever of objective finality. For since abstraction is made from        
this unity as end (what the thing is to be), nothing is left but the        
subjective finality of the representations in the mind of the               
subject intuiting. This gives a certain finality of the representative      
state of the subject, in which the subject feels itself quite at            
home in its effort to grasp a given form in the imagination, but no         
perfection of any object, the latter not being here thought through         
any concept. For instance, if in a forest I light upon a plot of            
grass, round which trees stand in a circle, and if I do not then            
form any representation of an end, as that it is meant to be used,          
say, for country dances, then not the least hint of a concept of            
perfection is given by the mere form. To suppose a formal objective         
finality that is yet devoid of an end, i.e., the mere form of a             
perfection (apart from any matter or concept of that to which the           
agreement relates, even though there was the mere general idea of a         
conformity to law) is a veritable contradiction.                            
  Now the judgement of taste is an aesthetic judgement, one resting on      
subjective grounds. No concept can be its determining ground, and           
hence not one of a definite end. Beauty, therefore, as a formal             
subjective finality, involves no thought whatsoever of a perfection of      
the object, as a would-be formal finality which yet, for all that,          
is objective: and the distinction between the concepts of the               
beautiful and the good, which represents both as differing only in          
their logical form, the first being merely a confused, the second a         
clearly defined, concept of perfection, while otherwise alike in            
content and origin, all goes for nothing: for then there would be no        
specific difference between them, but the judgement of taste would          
be just as much a cognitive judgement as one by which something is          
described as good-just as the man in the street, when be says that          
deceit is wrong, bases his judgement on confused, but the                   
philosopher on clear grounds, while both appeal in reality to               
identical principles of reason. But I have already stated that an           
aesthetic judgement is quite unique, and affords absolutely no (not         
even a confused) knowledge of the object. It is only through a logical      
judgement that we get knowledge. The aesthetic judgement, on the other      
hand, refers the representation, by which an object is given, solely        
to the subject, and brings to our notice no quality of the object, but      
only the final form in the determination of the powers of                   
representation engaged upon it. The judgement is called aesthetic           
for the very reason that its determining ground cannot be a concept,        
but is rather the feeling (of the internal sense) of the concert in         
the play of the mental powers as a thing only capable of being felt.        
If, on the other band, confused concepts, and the objective                 
judgement based on them, are going to be called aesthetic, we shall         
find ourselves with an understanding judging by sense, or a sense           
representing its objects by concepts-a mere choice of                       
contradictions. The faculty of concepts, be they confused or be they        
clear, is understanding; and although understanding has (as in all          
judgements) its role in the judgement of taste, as an aesthetic             
judgement, its role there is not that of a faculty for cognizing an         
object, but of a faculty for determining that judgement and its             
representation (without a concept) according to its relation to the         
subject and its internal feeling, and for doing so in so far as that        
judgement is possible according to a universal rule.                        
-                                                                           
      SS 16. A judgement of taste by which an object is                     
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 145}
       described as beautiful, under the condition of                       
             a definite concept, is not pure.                               
-                                                                           
  There are two kinds of beauty: free beauty (pulchritudo vaga), or         
beauty which is merely dependent (pulchritudo adhaerens). The first         
presupposes no concept of what the object should be; the second does        
presuppose such a concept and, with it, an answering perfection of the      
object. Those of the first kind are said to be (self-subsisting)            
beauties of this thing or that thing; the other kind of beauty,             
being attached to a concept (conditioned beauty), is ascribed to            
objects which come under the concept of a particular end.                   
  Flowers are free beauties of nature. Hardly anyone but a botanist         
knows the true nature of a flower, and even he, while recognizing in        
the flower the reproductive organ of the plant, pays no attention to        
this natural end when using his taste to judge of its beauty. Hence no      
perfection of any kind-no internal finality, as something to which the      
arrangement of the manifold is related-underlies this judgement.            
Many birds (the parrot, the humming-bird, the bird of paradise), and a      
number of crustacea, are self-subsisting beauties which are not             
appurtenant to any object defined with respect to its end, but              
please freely and on their own account. So designs a la grecque,            
foliage for framework or on wall-papers, etc., have no intrinsic            
meaning; they represent nothing-no object under a definite concept-and      
are free beauties. We may also rank in the same class what in music         
are called fantasias (without a theme), and, indeed, all music that is      
not set to words.                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 150}
  In the estimate of a free beauty (according to mere form) we have         
the pure judgement of taste. No concept is here presupposed of any end      
for which the manifold should serve the given object, and which the         
latter, therefore, should represent-an incumbrance which would only         
restrict the freedom of the imagination that, as it were, is at play        
in the contemplation of the outward form.                                   
  But the beauty of man (including under this head that of a man,           
woman, or child), the beauty of a horse, or of a building (such as a        
church, palace, arsenal, or summer-house), presupposes a concept of         
the end that defines what the thing has to be, and consequently a           
concept of its perfection; and is therefore merely appendant beauty.        
Now, just as it is a clog on the purity of the purity of the judgement      
of taste to have the agreeable (of sensation) joined with beauty to         
which properly only the form is relevant, so to combine the good            
with beauty (the good, namely, of the manifold to the thing itself          
according to its end) mars its purity.                                      
  Much might be added to a building that would immediately please           
the eye, were it not intended for a church. A figure might be               
beautified with all manner of flourishes and light but regular              
lines, as is done by the New Zealanders with their tattooing, were          
we dealing with anything but the figure of a human being. And here          
is one whose rugged features might be softened and given a more             
pleasing aspect, only he has got to be a man, or is, perhaps, a             
warrior that has to have a warlike appearance.                              
  Now the delight in the manifold of a thing, in reference to the           
internal end that determines its possibility, is a delight based on         
a concept, whereas delight in the beautiful is such as does not             
presuppose any concept, but is immediately coupled with the                 
representation through which the object is given (not through which it      
is thought). If, now, the judgement of taste in respect of the              
latter delight is made dependent upon the end involved in the former        
delight as a judgement of reason, and is thus placed under a                
restriction, then it is no longer a free and pure judgement of taste.       
  Taste, it is true, stands to gain by this combination of                  
intellectual delight with the aesthetic. For it becomes fixed, and,         
while not universal, it enables rules to be prescribed for it in            
respect of certain definite final objects. But these rules are then         
not rules of taste, but merely rules for establishing a union of taste      
with reason, i.e., of the beautiful with the good-rules by which the        
former becomes available as an intentional instrument in respect of         
the latter, for the purpose of bringing that temper of the mind             
which is self-sustaining and of subjective universal validity to the        
support and maintenance of that mode of thought which, while                
possessing objective universal validity, can only be preserved by a         
resolute effort. But, strictly speaking, perfection neither gains by        
beauty, nor beauty by perfection. The truth is rather this, when we         
compare the representation through which an object is given to us with      
the object (in respect of what it is meant to be) by means of a             
concept, we cannot help reviewing it also in respect of the                 
sensation in the subject. Hence there results a gain to the entire          
faculty of our representative power when harmony prevails between both      
states of mind.                                                             
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 155}
  In respect of an object with a definite internal end, a judgement of      
taste would only be pure where the person judging either has no             
concept of this end, or else makes abstraction from it in his               
judgement. But in cases like this, although such a person should lay        
down a correct judgement of taste, since he would be estimating the         
object as a free beauty, he would still be found fault with by another      
who saw nothing in its beauty but a dependent quality (i.e., who            
looked to the end of the object) and would be accused by him of             
false taste, though both would, in their own way, be judging                
correctly: the one according to what he had present to his senses, the      
other according to what was present in his thoughts. This                   
distinction enables us to settle many disputes about beauty on the          
part of critics; for we may show them how one side is dealing with          
free beauty, and the other with that which is dependent: the former         
passing a pure judgement of taste, the latter one that is applied           
intentionally.                                                              
-                                                                           
                  SS 17. Ideal of beauty.                                   
-                                                                           
  There can be no objective rule of taste by which what is beautiful        
may be defined by means of concepts. For every judgement from that          
source is aesthetic, i.e., its determining ground is the feeling of         
the subject, and not any concept of an object. It is only throwing          
away labour to look for a principle of taste that affords a                 
universal criterion of the beautiful by definite concepts; because          
what is sought is a thing impossible and inherently contradictory. But      
in the universal communicability of the sensation (of delight or            
aversion)-a communicability, too, that exists apart from any                
concept-in the accord, so far as possible, of all ages and nations          
as to this feeling in the representation of certain objects, we have        
the empirical criterion, weak indeed and scarce sufficient to raise         
a presumption, of the derivation of a taste, thus confirmed by              
examples, from grounds deep seated and shared alike by all men,             
underlying their agreement in estimating the forms under which objects      
are given to them.                                                          
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 160}
  For this reason some products of taste are looked on as                   
exemplary-not meaning thereby that by imitating others taste may be         
acquired. For taste must be an original faculty; whereas one who            
imitates a model, while showing skill commensurate with his success,        
only displays taste as himself a critic of this model.* Hence it            
follows that the highest model, the archetype of taste, is a mere           
idea, which each person must beget in his own consciousness, and            
according to which he must form his estimate of everything that is          
an object of taste, or that is an example of critical taste, and            
even of universal taste itself. Properly speaking, an idea signifies a      
concept of reason, and an ideal the representation of an individual         
existence as adequate to an idea. Hence this archetype of                   
taste-which rests, indeed, upon reason's indeterminate idea of a            
maximum, but is not, however, capable of being represented by means of      
concepts, but only in an individual presentation-may more                   
appropriately be called the ideal of the beautiful. While not having        
this ideal in our possession, we still strive to beget it within us.        
But it is bound to be merely an ideal of the imagination, seeing            
that it rests, not upon concepts, but upon the presentation-the             
faculty of presentation being the imagination. Now, how do we arrive        
at such an ideal of beauty? Is it a priori or empirically? Further,         
what species of the beautiful admits of an ideal?                           
-                                                                           
  *Models of taste with respect to the arts of speech must be composed      
in a dead and learned language; the first, to prevent their having          
to suffer the changes that inevitably overtake living ones, making          
dignified expressions become degraded, common ones antiquated, and          
ones newly coined after a short currency obsolete: the second to            
ensure its having a grammar that is not subject to the caprices of          
fashion, but has fixed rules of its own.                                    
-                                                                           
  First of all, we do well to observe that the beauty for which an          
ideal has to be sought cannot be a beauty that is free and at large,        
but must be one fixed by a concept of objective finality. Hence it          
cannot belong to the object of an altogether pure judgement of              
taste, but must attach to one that is partly intellectual. In other         
words, where an ideal is to have place among the grounds upon which         
any estimate is formed, then beneath grounds of that kind there must        
lie some idea of reason according to determinate concepts, by which         
the end underlying the internal possibility of the object is                
determined a priori. An ideal of beautiful flowers, of a beautiful          
suite of furniture, or of a beautiful view, is unthinkable. But, it         
may also be impossible to represent an ideal of a beauty dependent          
on definite ends, e.g., a beautiful residence, a beautiful tree, a          
beautiful garden, etc., presumably because their ends are not               
sufficiently defined and fixed by their concept, with the result            
that their finality is nearly as free as with beauty that is quite          
at large. Only what has in itself the end of its real existence-only        
man that is able himself to determine his ends by reason, or, where he      
has to derive them from external perception, can still compare them         
with essential and universal ends, and then further pronounce               
aesthetically upon their accord with such ends, only he, among all          
objects in the world, admits, therefore, of an ideal of beauty, just        
as humanity in his person, as intelligence, alone admits of the             
ideal of perfection.                                                        
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 165}
  Two factors are here involved. First, there is the aesthetic              
normal idea, which is an individual intuition (of the imagination).         
This represents the norm by which we judge of a man as a member of a        
particular animal species. Secondly, there is the rational idea.            
This deals with the ends of humanity so far as capable of sensuous          
representation, and converts them into a principle for estimating           
his outward form, through which these ends are revealed in their            
phenomenal effect. The normal idea must draw from experience the            
constituents which it requires for the form of an animal of a               
particular kind. But the greatest finality in the construction of this      
form-that which would serve as a universal norm for forming an              
estimate of each individual of the species in question-the image that,      
as it were, forms an intentional basis underlying the technic of            
nature, to which no separate individual, but only the race as a whole,      
is adequate, has its seat merely in the idea of the judging subject.        
Yet it is, with all its proportions, an aesthetic idea, and, as             
such, capable of being fully presented in concreto in a model image.        
Now, how is this effected? In order to render the process to some           
extent intelligible (for who can wrest nature's whole secret from           
her?), let us attempt a psychological explanation.                          
  It is of note that the imagination, in a manner quite                     
incomprehensible to us, is able on occasion, even after a long lapse        
of time, not alone to recall the signs for concepts, but also to            
reproduce the image and shape of an object out of a countless number        
of others of a different, or even of the very same, kind. And,              
further, if the mind is engaged upon comparisons, we may well               
suppose that it can in actual fact, though the process is unconscious,      
superimpose as it were one image upon another, and from the                 
coincidence of a number of the same kind arrive at a mean contour           
which serves as a common standard for all. Say, for instance, a person      
has seen a thousand full-grown men. Now if he wishes to judge normal        
size determined upon a comparative estimate, then imagination (to my        
mind) allows a great number of these images (perhaps the whole              
thousand) to fall one upon the other, and, if I may be allowed to           
extend to the case the analogy of optical presentation, in the space        
where they come most together, and within the contour where the             
place is illuminated by the greatest concentration of colour, one gets      
a perception of the average size, which alike in height and breadth is      
equally removed from the extreme limits of the greatest and smallest        
statures; and this is the stature of a beautiful man. (The same result      
could be obtained in a mechanical way, by taking the measures of all        
the thousand, and adding together their heights, and their breadths         
[and thicknesses], and dividing the sum in each case by a thousand.)        
But the power of imagination does all this by means of a dynamical          
effect upon the organ of internal sense, arising from the frequent          
apprehension of such forms. If, again, for our average man we seek          
on similar lines for the average head, and for this the average             
nose, and so on, then we get the figure that underlies the normal idea      
of a beautiful man in the country where the comparison is                   
instituted. For this reason a Negro must necessarily (under these           
empirical conditions) have a different normal idea of the beauty of         
forms from what a white man has, and the Chinaman one different from        
the European. And the. process would be just the same with the model        
of a beautiful horse or dog (of a particular breed). This normal            
idea is not derived from proportions taken from experience as definite      
rules: rather is it according to this idea that rules forming               
estimates first become possible. It is an intermediate between all          
singular intuitions of individuals, with their manifold variations-a        
floating image for the whole genus, which nature has set as an              
archetype underlying those of her products that belong to the same          
species, but which in no single case she seems to have completely           
attained. But the normal idea is far from giving the complete               
archetype of beauty in the genus. It only gives the form that               
constitutes the indispensable condition of all beauty, and,                 
consequently, only correctness in the presentation of the genus. It         
is, as the famous "Doryphorus" of Polycletus was called, the rule (and      
Myron's "Cow" might be similarly employed for its kind). It cannot,         
for that very reason, contain anything specifically characteristic;         
for otherwise it would not be the normal idea for the genus.                
Further, it is not by beauty that its presentation pleases, but merely      
because it does not contradict any of the conditions under which alone      
a thing belonging to this genus can be beautiful. The presentation          
is merely academically correct.*                                            
-                                                                           
  *It will be found that a perfectly regular face one that a painter        
might fix his eye on for a model-ordinarily conveys nothing. This is        
because it is devoid of anything characteristic, and so the idea of         
the race is expressed in it rather than the specific qualities of a         
person. The exaggeration of what is characteristic in this way,             
i.e., exaggeration violating the normal idea (the finality of the           
race), is called caricature. Also experience shows that these quite         
regular faces indicate as a rule internally only a mediocre type of         
man; presumably-if one may assume that nature in its external form          
expresses the proportions of the internal -because, where none of           
the mental qualities exceed the proportion requisite to constitute a        
man free from faults, nothing can be expected in the way of what is         
called genius, in which nature seems to make a departure from its           
wonted relations of the mental powers in favour of some special one.        
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 170}
  But the ideal of the beautiful is still something different from its      
normal idea. For reasons already stated it is only to be sought in the      
human figure. Here the ideal consists in the expression of the              
moral, apart from which the object would not please at once                 
universally and positively (not merely negatively in a presentation         
academically correct). The visible expression of moral ideas that           
govern men inwardly can, of course, only be drawn from experience; but      
their combination with all that our reason connects with the morally        
good in the idea of the highest finality-benevolence, purity,               
strength, or equanimity, etc.-may be made, as it were, visible in           
bodily manifestation (as effect of what is internal), and this              
embodiment involves a union of pure ideas of reason and great               
imaginative power, in one who would even form an estimate of it, not        
to speak of being the author of its presentation. The correctness of        
such an ideal of beauty is evidenced by its not permitting any              
sensuous charm to mingle with the delight in its object, in which it        
still allows us to take a great interest. This fact in turn shows that      
an estimate formed according to such a standard can never be purely         
aesthetic, and that one formed according to an ideal of beauty              
cannot be a simple judgement of taste.                                      
-                                                                           
    Definition of the Beautiful Derived from this Third Moment.             
-                                                                           
  Beauty is the form of finality in an object, so far as perceived          
in it apart from the representation of an end.*                             
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 175}
-                                                                           
  *As telling against this explanation, the instance may be adduced         
that there are things in which we see a form suggesting adaptation          
to an end, without any end being cognized in them-as, for example, the      
stone implements frequently obtained from sepulchral tumuli and             
supplied with a hole, as if for [inserting] a handle; and although          
these by their shape manifestly indicate a finality, the end of             
which is unknown, they are not on that account described as beautiful.      
But the very fact of their being regarded as art-products involves          
an immediate recognition that their shape is attributed to some             
purpose or other and to a definite end. For this reason there is no         
immediate delight whatever in their contemplation. A flower, on the         
other hand, such as a tulip, is regarded as beautiful, because we meet      
with a certain finality in its perception, which, in our estimate of        
it, is not referred to any end whatever.                                    
-                                                                           
       FOURTH MOMENT. Of the Judgement of Taste: Moment of                  
            the Modality of the Delight in the Object.                      
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 180}
-                                                                           
      SS 18. Nature of the modality in a judgement of taste.                
-                                                                           
  I may assert in the case of every representation that the                 
synthesis of a pleasure with the representation (as a cognition) is at      
least possible. Of what I call agreeable I assert that it actually          
causes pleasure in me. But what we have in mind in the case of the          
beautiful is a necessary reference on its part to delight. However,         
this necessity is of a special kind. It is not a theoretical objective      
necessity-such as would let us cognize a priori that every one will         
feel this delight in the object that is called beautiful by me. Nor         
yet is it a practical necessity, in which case, thanks to concepts          
of a pure rational will in which free agents are supplied with a rule,      
this delight is the necessary consequence of an objective law, and          
simply means that one ought absolutely (without ulterior object) to         
act in a certain way. Rather, being such a necessity as is thought          
in an aesthetic judgement, it can only be termed exemplary. In other        
words it is a necessity of the assent of all to a judgement regarded        
as exemplifying a universal rule incapable of formulation. Since an         
aesthetic judgement is not an objective or cognitive judgement, this        
necessity is not derivable from definite concepts, and so is not            
apodeictic. Much less is it inferable from universality of                  
experience (of a thoroughgoing agreement of judgements about the            
beauty of a certain object). For, apart from the fact that                  
experience would hardly furnish evidences sufficiently numerous for         
this purpose, empirical judgements do not afford any foundation for         
a concept of the necessity of these judgements.                             
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 185}
         SS 19. The subjective necessity attributed to a                    
              judgement of taste is conditioned.                            
-                                                                           
  The judgement of taste exacts agreement from every one; and a person      
who describes something as beautiful insists that every one ought to        
give the object in question his approval and follow suit in describing      
it as beautiful. The ought in aesthetic judgements, therefore, despite      
an accordance with all the requisite data for passing judgement, is         
still only pronounced conditionally. We are suitors for agreement from      
every one else, because we are fortified with a ground common to            
all. Further, we would be able to count on this agreement, provided we      
were always assured of the correct subsumption of the case under            
that ground as the rule of approval.                                        
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 190}
       SS 20. The condition of the necessity advanced by a                  
        judgement of taste is the idea of a common sense.                   
-                                                                           
  Were judgements of taste (like cognitive judgements) in possession        
of a definite objective principle, then one who in his judgement            
followed such a principle would claim unconditioned necessity for           
it. Again, were they devoid of any principle, as are those of the mere      
taste of sense, then no thought of any necessity on their part would        
enter one's head. Therefore they must have a subjective principle, and      
one which determines what pleases or displeases, by means of feeling        
only and not through concepts, but yet with universal validity. Such a      
principle, however, could only be regarded as a common sense. This          
differs essentially from common understanding, which is also sometimes      
called common sense (sensus communis): for the judgement of the latter      
is not one by feeling, but always one by concepts, though usually only      
in the shape of obscurely represented principles.                           
  The judgement of taste, therefore, depends on our presupposing the        
existence of a common sense. (But this is not to be taken to mean some      
external sense, but the effect arising from the free play of our            
powers of cognition.) Only under the presupposition, I repeat, of such      
a common sense, are we able to lay down a judgement of taste.               
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 195}
-                                                                           
     SS 21. Have we reason for presupposing a common sense?                 
-                                                                           
  Cognitions and judgements must, together with their attendant             
conviction, admit of being universally communicated; for otherwise a        
correspondence with the object would not be due to them. They would be      
a conglomerate constituting a mere subjective play of the powers of         
representation, just as scepticism would have it. But if cognitions         
are to admit of communication, then our mental state, i.e., the way         
the cognitive powers are attuned for cognition generally, and, in           
fact, the relative proportion suitable for a representation (by             
which an object is given to us) from which cognition is to result,          
must also admit of being universally communicated, as, without this,        
which is the subjective condition of the act of knowing, knowledge, as      
an effect, would not arise. And this is always what actually happens        
where a given object, through the intervention of sense, sets the           
imagination at work in arranging the manifold, and the imagination, in      
turn, the understanding in giving to this arrangement the unity of          
concepts. But this disposition of the cognitive powers has a                
relative proportion differing with the diversity of the objects that        
are given. However, there must be one in which this internal ratio          
suitable for quickening (one faculty by the other) is best adapted for      
both mental powers in respect of cognition (of given objects)               
generally; and this disposition can only be determined through feeling      
(and not by concepts). Since, now this disposition itself must admit        
of being universally communicated, and hence also the feeling of it         
(in the case of a given representation), while again, the universal         
communicability of a feeling presupposes a common sense: it follows         
that our assumption of it is well founded. And here, too, we do not         
have to take our stand on psychological observations, but we assume         
a common sense as the necessary condition of the universal                  
communicability of our knowledge, which is presupposed in every             
logic and every principle of knowledge that is not one of scepticism.       
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 200}
    SS 22. The necessity of the universal assent that is                    
      thought in a judgement of taste, is a subjective                      
       necessity which, under the presupposition of a                       
          common sense, is represented as objective.                        
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 205}
  In all judgements by which we describe anything as beautiful, we          
tolerate no one else being of a different opinion, and in taking up         
this position we do not rest our judgement upon concepts, but only          
on our feeling. Accordingly we introduce this fundamental feeling           
not as a private feeling, but as a public sense. Now, for this              
purpose, experience cannot be made the ground of this common sense,         
for the latter is invoked to justify judgements containing an "ought."      
The assertion is not that every one will fall in with our judgement,        
but rather that every one ought to agree with it. Here I put forward        
my judgement of taste as an example of the judgement of common              
sense, and attribute to it on that account exemplary validity. Hence        
common sense is a mere ideal norm. With this as presupposition, a           
judgement that accords with it, as well as the delight in an object         
expressed in that judgement, is rightly converted into a rule for           
everyone. For the principle, while it is only subjective, being yet         
assumed as subjectively universal (a necessary idea for everyone),          
could, in what concerns the consensus of different judging subjects,        
demand universal assent like an objective principle, provided we            
were assured of our subsumption under it being correct.                     
  This indeterminate norm of a common sense is, as a matter of fact,        
presupposed by us; as is shown by our presuming to lay down judgements      
of taste. But does such a common sense in fact exist as a constitutive      
principle of the possibility of experience, or is it formed for us          
as a regulative principle by a still higher principle of reason,            
that for higher ends first seeks to beget in us a common sense? Is          
taste, in other words, a natural and original faculty, or is it only        
the idea of one that is artificial and to be acquired by us, so that a      
judgement of taste, with its demand for universal assent, is but a          
requirement of reason for generating such a consensus, and does the         
"ought," i. e., the objective necessity of the coincidence of the           
feeling of all with the particular feeling of each, only betoken the        
possibility of arriving at some sort of unanimity in these matters,         
and the judgement of taste only adduce an example of the application        
of this principle? These are questions which as yet we are neither          
willing nor in a position to investigate. For the present we have only      
to resolve the faculty of taste into its elements, and to unite             
these ultimately in the idea of a common sense.                             
-                                                                           
    Definition of the Beautiful drawn from the Fourth Moment.               
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 210}
  The beautiful is that which, apart from a concept, is cognized as         
object of a necessary delight.                                              
-                                                                           
      General Remark on the First Section of the Analytic.                  
-                                                                           
  The result to be extracted from the foregoing analysis is in              
effect this: That everything runs up into the concept of taste as a         
critical faculty by which an object is estimated in reference to the        
free conformity to law of the imagination. If, now, imagination must        
in the judgement of taste be regarded in its freedom, then, to begin        
with, it is not taken as reproductive, as in its subjection to the          
laws of association, but as productive and exerting an activity of its      
own (as originator of arbitrary forms of possible intuitions). And          
although in the apprehension of a given object of sense it is tied          
down to a definite form of this object and, to that extent, does not        
enjoy free play (as it does in poetry), still it is easy to conceive        
that the object may supply ready-made to the imagination just such a        
form of the arrangement of the manifold as the imagination, if it were      
left to itself, would freely protect in harmony with the general            
conformity to law of the understanding. But that the imagination            
should be both free and of itself conformable to law, i. e., carry          
autonomy with it, is a contradiction. The understanding alone gives         
the law. Where, however, the imagination is compelled to follow a           
course laid down by a definite law, then what the form of the               
product is to be is determined by concepts; but, in that case, as           
already shown, the delight is not delight in the beautiful, but in the      
good (in perfection, though it be no more than formal perfection), and      
the judgement is not one due to taste. Hence it is only a conformity        
to law without a law, and a subjective harmonizing of the                   
imagination and the understanding without an objective one-which            
latter would mean that the representation was referred to a definite        
concept of the object-that can consist with the free conformity to law      
of the understanding (which has also been called finality apart from        
an end) and with the specific character of a judgement of taste.            
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 215}
  Now geometrically regular figures, a circle, a square, a cube, and        
the like, are commonly brought forward by critics of taste as the most      
simple and unquestionable examples of beauty. And yet the very              
reason why they are called regular, is because the only way of              
representing them is by looking on them as mere presentations of a          
determinate concept by which the figure has its rule (according to          
which alone it is possible) prescribed for it. One or other of these        
two views must, therefore, be wrong: either the verdict of the critics      
that attributes beauty to such figures, or else our own, which makes        
finality apart from any concept necessary for beauty.                       
  One would scarce think it necessary for a man to have taste to            
take more delight in a circle than in a scrawled outline, in an             
equilateral and equiangular quadrilateral than in one that is all           
lop-sided, and, as it were, deformed. The requirements of common            
understanding ensure such a preference without the least demand upon        
taste. Where some purpose is perceived, as, for instance, that of           
forming an estimate of the area of a plot of land, or rendering             
intelligible the relation of divided parts to one another and to the        
whole, then regular figures, and those of the simplest kind, are            
needed; and the delight does not rest immediately upon the way the          
figure strikes the eye, but upon its serviceability for all manner          
of possible purposes. A room with the walls making oblique angles, a        
plot laid out in a garden in a similar way, even any violation of           
symmetry, as well in the figure of animals (e.g., being one-eyed) as        
in that of buildings, or of flower-beds, is displeasing because of its      
perversity of form, not alone in a practical way in respect of some         
definite use to which the thing may be put, but for an estimate that        
looks to all manner of possible purposes. With the judgement of             
taste the case is different. For, when it is pure, it combines delight      
or aversion immediately with the bare contemplation of the object           
irrespective of its use or of any end.                                      
  The regularity that conduces to the concept of an object is, in           
fact, the indispensable condition (conditio sine qua non) of                
grasping the object as a single representation and giving to the            
manifold its determinate form. This determination is an end in respect      
of knowledge; and in this connection it is invariably coupled with          
delight (such as attends the accomplishment of any, even                    
problematical, purpose). Here, however, we have merely the value set        
upon the solution that satisfies the problem, and not a free and            
indeterminately final entertainment of the mental powers with what          
is called beautiful. In the latter case, understanding is at the            
service of imagination, in the former, this relation is reversed.           
  With a thing that owes its possibility to a purpose, a building,          
or even an animal, its regularity, which consists in symmetry, must         
express the unity of the intuition accompanying the concept of its          
end, and belongs with it to cognition. But where all that is                
intended is the maintenance of a free play of the powers of                 
representation (subject, however, to the condition that there is to be      
nothing for understanding to take exception to), in ornamental              
gardens, in the decoration of rooms, in all kinds of furniture that         
shows good taste, etc., regularity in the shape of constraint is to be      
avoided as far as possible. Thus English taste in gardens, and              
fantastic taste in furniture, push the freedom of imagination to the        
verge of what is grotesque the idea being that in this divorce from         
all constraint of rules the precise instance is being afforded where        
taste can exhibit its perfection in projects of the imagination to the      
fullest extent.                                                             
  All stiff regularity (such as borders on mathematical regularity) is      
inherently repugnant to taste, in that the contemplation of it affords      
us no lasting entertainment. Indeed, where it has neither cognition         
nor some definite practical end expressly in view, we get heartily          
tired of it. On the other hand, anything that gives the imagination         
scope for unstudied and final play is always fresh to us. We do not         
grow to hate the very sight of it. Marsden, in his description of           
Sumatra, observes that the free beauties of nature so surround the          
beholder on all sides that they cease to have much attraction for him.      
On the other band he found a pepper garden full of charm, on coming         
across it in mid-forest with its rows of parallel stakes on which           
the plant twines itself. From all this he infers that wild, and in its      
appearance quite irregular beauty, is only pleasing as a change to one      
whose eyes have become surfeited with regular beauty. But he need only      
have made the experiment of passing one day in his pepper garden to         
realize that once the regularity has enabled the understanding to           
put itself in accord with the order that is the constant                    
requirement, instead of the object diverting him any longer, it             
imposes an irksome constraint upon the imagination: whereas nature          
subject to no constraint of artificial rules, and lavish, as it             
there is, in its luxuriant variety can supply constant food for his         
taste. Even a bird's song, which we can reduce to no musical rule,          
seems to have more freedom in it, and thus to be richer for taste,          
than the human voice singing in accordance with all the rules that the      
art of music prescribes; for we grow tired much sooner of frequent and      
lengthy repetitions of the latter. Yet here most likely our sympathy        
with the mirth of a dear little creature is confused with the beauty        
of its song, for if exactly imitated by man (as has been sometimes          
done with the notes of the nightingale) it would strike our ear as          
wholly destitute of taste.                                                  
                                                   {SEC1|BK1 ^paragraph 220}
  Further, beautiful objects have to be distinguished from beautiful        
views of objects (where the distance often prevents a clear                 
perception). In the latter case, taste appears to fasten, not so            
much on what the imagination grasps in this field, as on the incentive      
it receives to indulge in poetic fiction, i. e., in the peculiar            
fancies with which the mind entertains itself as it is being                
continually stirred by the variety that strikes the eye. It is just as      
when we watch the changing shapes of the fire or of a rippling              
brook: neither of which are things of beauty, but they convey a             
charm to the imagination, because they sustain its free play.               
-                                                                           
                                                                            
SEC1|BK2                                                                    
           FIRST PART CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT                       
           SECTION I. ANALYTIC OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT.                      
               BOOK II. Analytic of the Sublime.                            
-                                                                           
     SS 23. Transition from the faculty of estimating the                   
         beautiful to that of estimating the sublime.                       
-                                                                           
                                                     {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 5}
  The beautiful and the sublime agree on the point of pleasing on           
their own account. Further they agree in not presupposing either a          
judgement of sense or one logically determinant, but one of                 
reflection. Hence it follows that the delight does not depend upon a        
sensation, as with the agreeable, nor upon a definite concept, as does      
the delight in the good, although it has, for all that, an                  
indeterminate reference to concepts. Consequently the delight is            
connected with the mere presentation or faculty of presentation, and        
is thus taken to express the accord, in a given intuition, of the           
faculty of presentation, or the imagination, with the faculty of            
concepts that belongs to understanding or reason, in the sense of           
the former assisting the latter. Hence both kinds of judgements are         
singular, and yet such as profess to be universally valid in respect        
of every subject, despite the fact that their claims are directed           
merely to the feeling of pleasure and not to any knowledge of the           
object.                                                                     
  There are, however, also important and striking differences               
between the two. The beautiful in nature is a question of the form          
of object, and this consists in limitation, whereas the sublime is          
to be found in an object even devoid of form, so far as it immediately      
involves, or else by its presence provokes a representation of              
limitlessness, yet with a superadded thought of its totality.               
Accordingly, the beautiful seems to be regarded as a presentation of        
an indeterminate concept of understanding, the sublime as a                 
presentation of an indeterminate concept of reason. Hence the               
delight is in the former case coupled with the representation of            
quality, but in this case with that of quantity. Moreover, the              
former delight is very different from the latter in kind. For the           
beautiful is directly attended with a feeling of the furtherance of         
life, and is thus compatible with charms and a playful imagination. On      
the other hand, the feeling of the sublime is a pleasure that only          
arises indirectly, being brought about by the feeling of a momentary        
check to the vital forces followed at once by a discharge all the more      
powerful, and so it is an emotion that seems to be no sport, but            
dead earnest in the affairs of the imagination. Hence charms are            
repugnant to it; and, since the mind is not simply attracted by the         
object, but is also alternately repelled thereby, the delight in the        
sublime does not so much involve positive pleasure as admiration or         
respect, i. e., merits the name of a negative pleasure.                     
  But the most important and vital distinction between the sublime and      
the beautiful is certainly this: that if, as is allowable, we here          
confine our attention in the first instance to the sublime in               
objects of nature (that of art being always restricted by the               
conditions of an agreement with nature), we observe that whereas            
natural beauty (such as is self-subsisting) conveys a finality in           
its form making the object appear, as it were, preadapted to our power      
of judgement, so that it thus forms of itself an object of our              
delight, that which, without our indulging in any refinements of            
thought, but, simply in our apprehension of it, excites the feeling of      
the sublime, may appear, indeed, in point of form to contravene the         
ends of our power of judgement, to be ill-adapted to our faculty of         
presentation, and to be, as it were, an outrage on the imagination,         
and yet it is judged all the more sublime on that account.                  
  From this it may be seen at once that we express ourselves on the         
whole inaccurately if we term any object of nature sublime, although        
we may with perfect propriety call many such objects beautiful. For         
how can that which is apprehended as inherently contra-final be             
noted with an expression of approval? All that we can say is that           
the object lends itself to the presentation of a sublimity                  
discoverable in the mind.                                                   
  For the sublime, in the strict sense of the word, cannot be               
contained in any sensuous form, but rather concerns ideas of reason,        
which, although no adequate presentation of them is possible, may be        
excited and called into the mind by that very inadequacy itself             
which does admit of sensuous presentation. Thus the broad ocean             
agitated by storms cannot be called sublime. Its aspect is horrible,        
and one must have stored one's mind in advance with a rich stock of         
ideas, if such an intuition is to raise it to the pitch of a feeling        
which is itself sublime-sublime because the mind has been incited to        
abandon sensibility and employ itself upon ideas involving higher           
finality.                                                                   
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 10}
  Self-subsisting natural beauty reveals to us a technic of nature          
which shows it in the light of a system ordered in accordance with          
laws the principle of which is not to be found within the range of our      
entire faculty of understanding. This principle is that of a                
finality relative to the employment of judgement in respect of              
phenomena which have thus to be assigned, not merely to nature              
regarded as aimless mechanism, but also to nature regarded after the        
analogy of art. Hence it gives a veritable extension, not, of               
course, to our knowledge of objects of nature, but to our conception        
of nature itself-nature as mere mechanism being enlarged to the             
conception of nature as art-an extension inviting profound inquiries        
as to the possibility of such a form. But in what we are wont to            
call sublime in nature there is such an absence of anything leading to      
particular objective principles and corresponding forms of nature that      
it is rather in its chaos, or in its wildest and most irregular             
disorder and desolation, provided it gives signs of magnitude and           
power, that nature chiefly excites the ideas of the sublime. Hence          
we see that the concept of the sublime in nature is far less important      
and rich in consequences than that of its beauty. It gives on the           
whole no indication of anything final in nature itself, but only in         
the possible employment of our intuitions of it in inducing a               
feeling in our own selves of a finality quite independent of nature.        
For the beautiful in nature we must seek a ground external to               
ourselves, but for the sublime one merely in ourselves and the              
attitude of mind that introduces sublimity into the representation          
of nature. This is a very needful preliminary remark. It entirely           
separates the ideas of the sublime from that of a finality of               
nature, and makes the theory of the sublime a mere appendage to the         
aesthetic estimate of the finality of nature, because it does not give      
a representation of any particular form in nature, but involves no          
more than the development of a final employment by the imagination          
of its own representation.                                                  
-                                                                           
       SS 24. Subdivision of an investigation of the feeling                
                        of the sublime.                                     
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 15}
  In the division of the moments of an aesthetic estimate of objects        
in respect of the feeling of the sublime, the course of the Analytic        
will be able to follow the same principle as in the analysis of             
judgements of taste. For, the judgement being one of the aesthetic          
reflective judgement, the delight in the sublime, just like that in         
the beautiful, must in its quantity be shown to be universally              
valid, in its quality independent of interest, in its relation              
subjective finality, and the latter, in its modality, necessary. Hence      
the method here will not depart from the lines followed in the              
preceding section: unless something is made of the point that there,        
where the aesthetic judgement bore on the form of the object, we began      
with the investigation of its quality, whereas here, considering the        
formlessness that may belong to what we call sublime, we begin with         
that of its quantity, as first moment of the aesthetic judgement on         
the sublime-a divergence of method the reason for which is evident          
from SS 23.                                                                 
  But the analysis of the sublime obliges a division not required by        
that of the beautiful, namely one into the mathematically and the           
dynamically sublime.                                                        
  For the feeling of sublime involves as its characteristic feature         
a mental movement combined with the estimate of the object, whereas         
taste in respect of the beautiful presupposes that the mind is in           
restful contemplation, and preserves it in this state. But this             
movement has to be estimated as subjectively final (since the               
sublime pleases). Hence it is referred through the imagination              
either to the faculty of cognition or to that of desire; but to             
whichever faculty the reference is made, the finality of the given          
representation is estimated only in respect of these faculties              
(apart from end or interest). Accordingly the first is attributed to        
the object as a mathematical, the second as a dynamical, affection          
of the imagination. Hence we get the above double mode of representing      
an object as sublime.                                                       
-                                                                           
                A. THE MATHEMATICALLY SUBLIME.                              
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 20}
           SS 25. Definition of the term "sublime".                         
-                                                                           
  Sublime is the name given to what is absolutely great. But to be          
great and to be a magnitude are entirely different concepts (magnitudo      
and quantitas). In the same way, to assert without qualification            
(simpliciter) that something is great is quite a different thing            
from saying that it is absolutely great (absolute, non comparative          
magnum). The latter is what is beyond all comparison great. What,           
then, is the meaning of the assertion that anything is great, or            
small, or of medium size? What is indicated is not a pure concept of        
understanding, still less an intuition of sense; and just as little is      
it a concept of reason, for it does not import any principle of             
cognition. It must, therefore, be a concept of judgement, or have           
its source in one, and must introduce as basis of the judgement a           
subjective finality of the representation with reference to the             
power of judgement. Given a multiplicity of the homogeneous together        
constituting one thing, and we may at once cognize from the thing           
itself that it is a magnitude (quantum). No comparison with other           
things is required. But to determine how great it is always requires        
something else, which itself has magnitude, for its measure. Now,           
since in the estimate of magnitude we have to take into account not         
merely the multiplicity (number of units) but also the magnitude of         
the unit (the measure), and since the magnitude of this unit in turn        
always requires something else as its measure and as the standard of        
its comparison, and so on, we see that the computation of the               
magnitude of phenomena is, in all cases, utterly incapable of               
affording us any absolute concept of a magnitude, and can, instead,         
only afford one that is always based on comparison.                         
  If, now, I assert without qualification that anything is great, it        
would seem that I have nothing in the way of a comparison present to        
my mind, or at least nothing involving an objective measure, for no         
attempt is thus made to determine how great the object is. But,             
despite the standard of comparison being merely subjective, the             
claim of the judgement is none the less one to universal agreement;         
the judgements: "that man is beautiful" and "He is tall", do not            
purport to speak only for the judging subject, but, like theoretical        
judgements, they demand the assent of everyone.                             
  Now in a judgement that without qualification describes anything          
as great, it is not merely meant that the object has a magnitude,           
but greatness is ascribed to it pre-eminently among many other objects      
of a like kind, yet without the extent of this pre-eminence being           
determined. Hence a standard is certainly laid at the basis of the          
judgement, which standard is presupposed to be one that can be taken        
as the same for every one, but which is available only for an               
aesthetic estimate of the greatness, and not for one that is logical        
(mathematically determined), for the standard is a merely subjective        
one underlying the reflective judgement upon the greatness.                 
Furthermore, this standard may be empirical, as, let us say, the            
average size of the men known to us, of animals of a certain kind,          
of trees, of houses, of mountains, and so forth. Or it may be a             
standard given a priori, which by reason of the imperfections of the        
judging subject is restricted to subjective conditions of presentation      
in concreto; as, in the practical sphere, the greatness of a                
particular virtue, or of public liberty and justice in a country;           
or, in the theoretical sphere, the greatness of the accuracy or             
inaccuracy of an experiment or measurement, etc.                            
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 25}
  Here, now, it is of note that, although we have no interest whatever      
in the object, i.e., its real existence may be a matter of no               
concern to us, still its mere greatness, regarded even as devoid of         
form, is able to convey a universally communicable delight and so           
involve the consciousness of a subjective finality in the employment        
of our cognitive faculties, but not, be it remembered, a delight in         
the object, for the latter may be formless, but, in                         
contradistinction to what is the case with the beautiful, where the         
reflective judgement finds itself set to a key that is final in             
respect of cognition generally, a delight in an extension affecting         
the imagination itself.                                                     
  If (subject as above) we say of an object, without qualification,         
that it is great, this is not a mathematically determinant, but a mere      
reflective judgement upon its representation, which is subjectively         
final for a particular employment of our cognitive faculties in the         
estimation of magnitude, and we then always couple with the                 
representation a kind of respect, just as we do a kind of contempt          
with what we call absolutely small. Moreover, the estimate of things        
as great or small extends to everything, even to all their                  
qualities. Thus we call even their beauty great or small. The reason        
of this is to be found in the fact that we have only got to present         
a thing in intuition, as the precept of judgement directs                   
(consequently to represent it aesthetically), for it to be in its           
entirety a phenomenon, and hence a quantum.                                 
  If, however, we call anything not alone great, but, without               
qualification, absolutely, and in every respect (beyond all                 
comparison) great, that is to say, sublime, we soon perceive that           
for this it is not permissible to seek an appropriate standard outside      
itself, but merely in itself. It is a greatness comparable to itself        
alone. Hence it comes that the sublime is not to be looked for in           
the things of nature, but only in our own ideas. But it must be left        
to the deduction to show in which of them it resides.                       
  The above definition may also be expressed in this way: that is           
sublime in comparison with which all else is small. Here we readily         
see that nothing can be given in nature, no matter how great we may         
judge it to be, which, regarded in some other relation, may not be          
degraded to the level of the infinitely little, and nothing so small        
which in comparison with some still smaller standard may not for our        
imagination be enlarged to the greatness of a world. Telescopes have        
put within our reach an abundance of material to go upon in making the      
first observation, and microscopes the same in making the second.           
Nothing, therefore, which can be an object of the senses is to be           
termed sublime when treated on this footing. But precisely because          
there is a striving in our imagination towards progress ad                  
infinitum, while reason demands absolute totality, as a real idea,          
that same inability on the part of our faculty for the estimation of        
the magnitude of things of the world of sense to attain to this             
idea, is the awakening of a feeling of a supersensible faculty              
within us; and it is the use to which judgement naturally puts              
particular objects on behalf of this latter feeling, and not the            
object of sense, that is absolutely great, and every other                  
contrasted employment small. Consequently it is the disposition of          
soul evoked by a particular representation engaging the attention of        
the reflective judgement, and not the object, that is to be called          
sublime.                                                                    
  The foregoing formulae defining the sublime may, therefore, be            
supplemented by yet another: The sublime is that, the mere capacity of      
thinking which evidences a faculty of mind transcending every standard      
of sense.                                                                   
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 30}
-                                                                           
       SS 26. The estimation of the magnitude of natural                    
          things requisite for the idea of the sublime.                     
-                                                                           
  The estimation of magnitude by means of concepts of number (or their      
signs in algebra) is mathematical, but that in mere intuition (by           
the eye) is aesthetic. Now we can only get definite concepts of how         
great anything is by having recourse to numbers (or, at any rate, by        
getting approximate measurements by means of numerical series               
progressing ad infinitum), the unit being the measure; and to this          
extent all logical estimation of magnitude is mathematical. But, as         
the magnitude of the measure has to be assumed as a known quantity,         
if, to form an estimate of this, we must again have recourse to             
numbers involving another standard for their unit, and consequently         
must again proceed mathematically, we can never arrive at a first or        
fundamental measure, and so cannot get any definite concept of a given      
magnitude. The estimation of the magnitude of the fundamental               
measure must, therefore, consist merely in the immediate grasp which        
we can get of it in intuition, and the use to which our imagination         
can put this in presenting the numerical concepts: i.e., all                
estimation of the magnitude of objects of nature is in the last resort      
aesthetic (i.e., subjectively and not objectively determined).              
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 35}
  Now for the mathematical estimation of magnitude there is, of             
course, no greatest possible (for the power of numbers extends to           
infinity), but for the aesthetic estimation there certainly is and          
of it I say that where it is considered an absolute measure beyond          
which no greater is possible subjectively (i.e., for the judging            
subject), it then conveys the idea of the sublime and calls forth that      
emotion which no mathematical estimation of magnitudes by numbers           
can evoke (unless in so far as the fundamental aesthetic measure is         
kept vividly present to the imagination): because the latter                
presents only the relative magnitude due to comparison with others          
of a like kind, whereas the former presents magnitude absolutely, so        
far as the mind can grasp it in an intuition.                               
  To take in a quantum intuitively in the imagination so as to be able      
to use it as a measure, or unit for estimating magnitude by numbers,        
involves two operations of this faculty: apprehension (apprehensio)         
and comprehension (comprehension aesthetica). Apprehension presents no      
difficulty: for this process can be carried on ad infinitum; but            
with the advance of apprehension comprehension becomes more                 
difficult at every step and soon attains its maximum, and this is           
the aesthetically greatest fundamental measure for the estimation of        
magnitude. For if the apprehension has reached a point beyond which         
the representations of sensuous intuition in the case of the parts          
first apprehended begin to disappear from the imagination as this           
advances to the apprehension of yet others, as much, then, is lost          
at one end as is gained at the other, and for comprehension we get a        
maximum which the imagination cannot exceed.                                
  This explains Savary's observations in his account of Egypt, that in      
order to get the full emotional effect of the size of the Pyramids          
we must avoid coming too near just as much as remaining too far             
away. For in the latter case the representation of the apprehended          
parts (the tiers of stones) is but obscure, and produces no effect          
upon the aesthetic judgement of the Subject. In the former, however,        
it takes the eye some time to complete the apprehension from the            
base to the summit; but in this interval the first tiers always in          
part disappear before the imagination has taken in the last, and so         
the comprehension is never complete. The same explanation may also          
sufficiently account for the bewilderment, or sort of perplexity,           
which, as is said, seizes the visitor on first entering St. Peter's in      
Rome. For here a feeling comes home to him of the inadequacy of his         
imagination for presenting the idea of a whole within which that            
imagination attains its maximum, and, in its fruitless efforts to           
extend this limit, recoils upon itself, but in so doing succumbs to an      
emotional delight.                                                          
  At present I am not disposed to deal with the ground of this              
delight, connected, as it is, with a representation in which we             
would least of all look for it-a representation, namely, that lets          
us see its own inadequacy, and consequently its subjective want of          
finality for our judgement in the estimation of magnitude-but               
confine myself to the remark that if the aesthetic judgement is to          
be pure (unmixed with any teleological judgement which, as such,            
belongs to reason), and if we are to give a suitable example of it for      
the Critique of aesthetic judgement, we must not point to the               
sublime in works of art, e.g., buildings, statues and the like,             
where a human end determines the form as well as the magnitude, nor         
yet in things of nature, that in their very concept import a                
definite end, e.g., animals of a recognized natural order, but in rude      
nature merely as involving magnitude (and only in this so far as it         
does not convey any charm or any emotion arising from actual                
danger). For, in a representation of this kind, nature contains             
nothing monstrous (nor what is either magnificent or horrible)-the          
magnitude apprehended may be increased to any extent provided               
imagination is able to grasp it all in one whole. An object is              
monstrous where by its size it defeats the end that forms its concept.      
The colossal is the mere presentation of a concept which is almost too      
great for presentation, i.e., borders on the relatively monstrous; for      
the end to be attained by the presentation of a concept is made harder      
to realize by the intuition of the object being almost too great for        
our faculty of apprehension. A pure judgement upon the sublime must,        
however, have no end belonging to the object as its determining             
ground, if it is to be aesthetic and not to be tainted with any             
judgement of understanding or reason.                                       
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 40}
  Since whatever is to be a source of pleasure, apart from interest,        
to the merely reflective judgement must involve in its                      
representation subjective, and, as such, universally valid                  
finality-though here, however, no finality of the form of the object        
underlies our estimate of it (as it does in the case of the                 
beautiful)-the question arises: What is the subjective finality, and        
what enables it to be prescribed as a norm so as to yield a ground for      
universally valid delight in the mere estimation of magnitude, and          
that, too, in a case where it is pushed to the point at which               
faculty of imagination breaks down in presenting the concept of a           
magnitude, and proves unequal to its task?                                  
  In the successive aggregation of units requisite for the                  
representation of magnitudes, the imagination of itself advances ad         
infinitum without let or hindrance-understanding, however,                  
conducting it by means of concepts of number for which the former must      
supply the schema. This procedure belongs to the logical estimation of      
magnitude, and, as such, is doubtless something objectively final           
according to the concept of an end (as all measurement is), but it          
is hot anything which for the aesthetic judgement is final or               
pleasing. Further, in this intentional finality there is nothing            
compelling us to tax the utmost powers of the imagination, and drive        
it as far as ever it can reach in its presentations, so as to               
enlarge the size of the measure, and thus make the single intuition         
holding the many in one (the comprehension) as great as possible. For,      
in the estimation of magnitude by the understanding (arithmetic), we        
get just as far, whether the comprehension of the units is pushed to        
the number 10 (as in the decimal scale) or only to 4 (as in the             
quaternary); the further production of magnitude being carried out          
by the successive aggregation of units, or, if the quantum is given in      
intuition, by apprehension, merely progressively (not                       
comprehensively), according to an adopted principle of progression. In      
this mathematical estimation of magnitude, understanding is as well         
served and as satisfied whether imagination selects for the unit a          
magnitude which one can take in at a glance, e.g., a foot, or a perch,      
or else a German mile, or even the earth's diameter, the                    
apprehension of which is indeed possible, but not its comprehension         
in, sit intuition of the imagination (i.e., it is not possible by           
means of a comprehension aesthetica, thought quite so by means of a         
comprehension logica in a numerical concept). In each case the logical      
estimation of magnitude advances ad infinitum with nothing to stop it.      
  The mind, however, hearkens now to the voice of reason, which for         
all given magnitudes-even for those which can never be completely           
apprehended, though (in sensuous representation) estimated as               
completely given-requires totality, and consequently comprehension          
in one intuition, and which calls for a presentation answering to           
all the above members of a progressively increasing numerical               
series, and does not exempt even the infinite (space and time past)         
from this requirement, but rather renders it inevitable for us to           
regard this infinite (in the judgement of common reason) as completely      
given (i.e., given in its totality).                                        
  But the infinite is absolutely (not merely comparatively) great.          
In comparison with this all else (in the way of magnitudes of the same      
order) is small. But the point of capital importance is that the            
mere ability even to think it as a whole indicates a faculty of mind        
transcending every standard of sense. For the latter would entail a         
comprehension yielding as unit a standard bearing to the infinite           
ratio expressible in numbers, which is impossible. Still the mere           
ability even to think the given infinite without contradiction, is          
something that requires the presence in the human mind of a faculty         
that is itself supersensible. For it is only through this faculty           
and its idea of a noumenon, which latter, while not itself admitting        
of any intuition, is yet introduced as substrate underlying the             
intuition of the world as mere phenomenon, that the infinite of the         
world of sense, in the pure intellectual estimation of magnitude, is        
completely comprehended under a concept, although in the                    
mathematical estimation by means of numerical concepts it can never be      
completely thought. Even a faculty enabling the infinite of                 
supersensible intuition to be regarded as given (in its intelligible        
substrate), transcends every standard of sensibility and is great           
beyond all comparison even with the faculty of mathematical                 
estimation: not, of course, from a theoretical point of view that           
looks to the interests of our faculty of knowledge, but as a                
broadening of the mind that from another (the practical) point of view      
feels itself empowered to pass beyond the narrow confines of                
sensibility.                                                                
  Nature, therefore, is sublime in such of its phenomena as in their        
intuition convey the idea of their infinity. But this can only occur        
through the inadequacy of even the greatest effort of our                   
imagination in the estimation of the magnitude of an object. But, now,      
in the case of the mathematical estimation of magnitude, imagination        
is quite competent to supply a measure equal to the requirements of         
any object. For the numerical concepts of the understanding can by          
progressive synthesis make any measure adequate to any given                
magnitude. Hence it must be the aesthetic estimation of magnitude in        
which we get at once a feeling of the effort towards a comprehension        
that exceeds the faculty of imagination for mentally grasping the           
progressive apprehension in a whole of intuition, and, with it, a           
perception of the inadequacy of this faculty, which has no bounds to        
its progress, for taking in and using for the estimation of                 
magnitude a fundamental measure that understanding could turn to            
account without the least trouble. Now the proper unchangeable              
fundamental measure of nature is its absolute whole, which, with it,        
regarded as a phenomenon, means infinity comprehended. But, since this      
fundamental measure is a self-contradictory concept (owing to the           
impossibility of the absolute totality of an endless progression),          
it follows that where the size of a natural object is such that the         
imagination spends its whole faculty of comprehension upon it in vain,      
it must carry our concept of nature, to a supersensible substrate           
(underlying both nature and our faculty of thought). which is, great        
beyond every standard of sense. Thus, instead of the object, it is          
rather the cast of the mind in appreciating it that we have to              
estimate as sublime.                                                        
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 45}
  Therefore, just as the aesthetic judgement in its estimate of the         
beautiful refers the imagination in its free play to the                    
understanding, to bring out its agreement with the concepts of the          
latter in general (apart from their determination): so in its estimate      
of a thing as sublime it refers that faculty to reason to bring out         
its subjective accord with ideas of reason (indeterminately                 
indicated), i.e., to induce a temper of mind conformable-to that which      
the influence of definite (practical) ideas would produce upon              
feeling, and in common accord with it.                                      
  This makes it evident that true sublimity must be sought only in the      
mind of the judging subject, and not in the object of nature that           
occasions this attitude by the estimate formed of it. Who would             
apply the term "sublime" even to shapeless mountain masses towering         
one above the other in wild disorder, with their pyramids of ice, or        
to the dark tempestuous ocean, or such like things? But in the              
contemplation of them, without any regard to their form, the mind           
abandons itself to the imagination and to a reason placed, though           
quite apart from any definite end, in conjunction therewith, and            
merely broadening its view, and it feels itself elevated in its own         
estimate of itself on finding all the might of imagination still            
unequal to its ideas.                                                       
  We get examples of the mathematically sublime of nature in mere           
intuition in all those instances where our imagination is afforded,         
not so much a greater numerical concept as a large unit as measure          
(for shortening the numerical series). A tree judged by the height          
of man gives, at all events, a standard for a mountain; and, supposing      
this is, say, a mile high, it can serve as unit for the number              
expressing the earth's diameter, so as to make it intuitable;               
similarly the earth's diameter for the known planetary system; this         
again for the system of the Milky Way; and the immeasurable host of         
such systems, which go by the name of nebulae, and most likely in turn      
themselves form such a system, holds out no prospect of a limit. Now        
in the aesthetic estimate of such an immeasurable whole, the sublime        
does not lie so much in the greatness of the number, as in the fact         
that in our onward advance we always arrive at proportionately greater      
units. The systematic division of the cosmos conduces to this               
result. For it represents all that is great in nature as in turn            
becoming little; or, to be more exact, it represents our imagination        
in all its boundlessness, and with it nature, as sinking into               
insignificance before the ideas of reason, once their adequate              
presentation is attempted.                                                  
-                                                                           
         SS 27. Quality of the delight in our estimate                      
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 50}
                      of the sublime.                                       
-                                                                           
  The feeling of our incapacity to attain to an idea that is a law for      
us, is respect. Now the idea of the comprehension of any phenomenon         
whatever, that may be given us, in a whole of intuition, is an idea         
imposed upon us by a law of reason, which recognizes no definite,           
universally valid and unchangeable measure except the absolute              
whole. But our imagination, even when taxing itself to the uttermost        
on the score of this required comprehension of a given object in a          
whole of intuition (and so with a view to the presentation of the idea      
of reason), betrays its limits and its inadequacy, but still, at the        
same time, its proper vocation of making itself adequate to the same        
as law. Therefore the feeling of the sublime in nature is respect           
for our own vocation, which we attribute to an object of nature by a        
certain subreption (substitution of a respect for the object in             
place of one for the idea of humanity in our own self-the subject);         
and this feeling renders, as it were, intuitable the supremacy of           
our cognitive faculties on the rational side over the greatest faculty      
of sensibility.                                                             
  The feeling of the sublime is, therefore, at once a feeling of            
displeasure, arising from the inadequacy of imagination in the              
aesthetic estimation of magnitude to attain to its estimation by            
reason, and a simultaneously awakened pleasure, arising from this very      
judgement of the inadequacy of the greatest faculty of sense being          
in accord with ideas of reason, so far as the effort to attain to           
these is for us a law. It is, in other words, for us a law (of              
reason), which goes to make us what we are, that we should esteem as        
small in comparison with ideas of reason everything which for us is         
great in nature as an object of sense; and that which makes us alive        
to the feeling of this supersensible side of our being harmonizes with      
that law. Now the greatest effort of the imagination in the                 
presentation of the unit for the estimation of magnitude involves in        
itself a reference to something absolutely great, consequently a            
reference also to the law of reason that this alone is to be adopted        
as the supreme measure of what is great. Therefore the inner                
perception of the inadequacy of every standard of sense to serve for        
the rational estimation of magnitude is a coming into accord with           
reason's laws, and a displeasure that makes us alive to the feeling of      
the supersensible side of our being, according to which it is final,        
and consequently a pleasure, to find every standard of sensibility          
falling short of the ideas of reason.                                       
  The mind feels itself set in motion in the representation of the          
sublime in nature; whereas in the aesthetic judgement upon what is          
beautiful therein it is in restful contemplation. This movement,            
especially in its inception, may be compared with vibration, i.e.,          
with a rapidly alternating repulsion and attraction produced by one         
and the same object. The point of excess for the imagination                
(towards which it is driven in the apprehension of the intuition) is        
like an abyss in which it fears to lose itself, yet again for the           
rational idea of the supersensible it is not excessive, but                 
conformable to law, and directed to drawing out such an effort on           
the part of the imagination: and so in turn as much a source of             
attraction as it was repellent to mere sensibility. But the                 
judgement itself all the while steadfastly preserves its aesthetic          
character, because it represents, without being grounded on any             
definite concept of the object, merely the subjective play of the           
mental powers (imagination and reason) as harmonious by virtue of           
their very contrast. For just as in the estimate of the beautiful           
imagination and understanding by their concert generate subjective          
finality of the mental faculties, so imagination and reason do so here      
by their conflict-that is to say they induce a feeling of our               
possessing a pure and self-sufficient reason, or a faculty for the          
estimation of magnitude, whose preeminence can only be made                 
intuitively evident by the inadequacy of that faculty which in the          
presentation of magnitudes (of objects of sense) is itself unbounded.       
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 55}
  Measurement of a space (as apprehension) is at the same time a            
description of it, and so an objective movement in the imagination and      
a progression. On the other hand, the comprehension of the manifold in      
the unity, not of thought, but of intuition, and consequently the           
comprehension of the successively apprehended parts at one glance,          
is a retrogression that removes the time-condition in the                   
progression of the imagination, and renders coexistence intuitable.         
Therefore, since the time-series is a condition of the internal             
sense and of an intuition, it is a subjective movement of the               
imagination by which it does violence to the internal sense-a violence      
which must be proportionately more striking the greater the quantum         
which the imagination comprehends in one intuition. The effort,             
therefore, to receive in a single intuition a measure for magnitudes        
which it takes an appreciable time to apprehend, is a mode of               
representation which, subjectively considered, is contra-final, but         
objectively, is requisite for the estimation of magnitude, and is           
consequently final. Here the very same violence that is wrought on the      
subject through the imagination is estimated as final for the whole         
province of the mind.                                                       
  The quality of the feeling of the sublime consists in being, in           
respect of the faculty of forming aesthetic estimates, a feeling of         
displeasure at an object, which yet, at the same time, is                   
represented as being final-a representation which derives its               
possibility from the fact that the subject's very incapacity betrays        
the consciousness of an unlimited faculty of the same subject, and          
that the mind can only form an aesthetic estimate of the latter             
faculty by means of that incapacity.                                        
  In the case of the logical estimation of magnitude, the                   
impossibility of ever arriving at absolute totality by the progressive      
measurement of things of the sensible world in time and space was           
cognized as an objective impossibility, i.e., one of thinking the           
infinite as given, and not as simply subjective, i.e., an incapacity        
for grasping it; for nothing turns there on the amount of the               
comprehension in one intuition, as measure, but everything depends          
on a numerical concept. But in an aesthetic estimation of magnitude         
the numerical concept must drop out of count or undergo a change.           
The only thing that is final for such estimation is the                     
comprehension on the part of imagination in respect of the unit of          
measure (the concept of a law of the successive production of the           
concept of magnitude being consequently avoided). If, now, a magnitude      
begins to tax the utmost stretch of our faculty of comprehension in an      
intuition, and still numerical magnitudes-in respect of which we are        
conscious of the boundlessness of our faculty-call upon the                 
imagination for aesthetic comprehension in a greater unit, the mind         
then gets a feeling of being aesthetically confined within bounds.          
Nevertheless, with a view to the extension of imagination necessary         
for adequacy with what is unbounded in our faculty of reason, namely        
the idea of the absolute whole, the attendant displeasure, and,             
consequently, the want of finality in our faculty of imagination, is        
still represented as final for ideas of reason and their animation.         
But in this very way the aesthetic judgement itself is subjectively         
final for reason as source of ideas, i.e., of such an intellectual          
comprehension as makes all aesthetic comprehension small, and the           
object is received as sublime with a pleasure that is only possible         
through the mediation of a displeasure.                                     
-                                                                           
             B. THE DYNAMICALLY SUBLIME IN NATURE.                          
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 60}
                    SS 28. Nature as Might.                                 
-                                                                           
  Might is a power which is superior to great hindrances. It is termed      
dominion if it is also superior to the resistance of that which itself      
possesses might. Nature, considered in an aesthetic judgement as might      
that has no dominion over us, is dynamically sublime.                       
  If we are to estimate nature as dynamically sublime, it must be           
represented as a source of fear (though the converse, that every            
object that is a source of fear, in our aesthetic judgement,                
sublime, does not hold). For in forming an aesthetic estimate (no           
concept being present) the superiority to hindrances can only be            
estimated according to the greatness of the resistance. Now that which      
we strive to resist is an evil, and, if we do not find our powers           
commensurate to the task, an object of fear. Hence the aesthetic            
judgement can only deem nature a might, and so dynamically sublime, in      
so far as it is looked upon as an object of fear.                           
  But we may look upon an object as fearful, and yet not be afraid          
of it, if, that is, our estimate takes the form of our simply               
picturing to ourselves the case of our wishing to offer some                
resistance to it and recognizing that all such resistance would be          
quite futile. So the righteous man fears God without being afraid of        
Him, because he regards the case of his wishing to resist God and           
His commandments as one which need cause him no anxiety. But in             
every such case, regarded by him as not intrinsically impossible, he        
cognizes Him as One to be feared.                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 65}
  One who is in a state of fear can no more play the part of a judge        
of the sublime of nature than one captivated by inclination and             
appetite can of the beautiful. He flees from the sight of an object         
filling him with dread; and it is impossible to take delight in terror      
that is seriously entertained. Hence the agreeableness arising from         
the cessation of an uneasiness is a state of joy. But this,                 
depending upon deliverance from a danger, is a rejoicing accompanied        
with a resolve never again to put oneself in the way of the danger: in      
fact we do not like bringing back to mind how we felt on that occasion      
not to speak of going in search of an opportunity for experiencing          
it again.                                                                   
  Bold, overhanging, and, as it were, threatening rocks, thunderclouds      
piled up the vault of heaven, borne along with flashes and peals,           
volcanos in all their violence of destruction, hurricanes leaving           
desolation in their track, the boundless ocean rising with                  
rebellious force, the high waterfall of some mighty river, and the          
like, make our power of resistance of trifling moment in comparison         
with their might. But, provided our own position is secure, their           
aspect is all the more attractive for its fearfulness; and we               
readily call these objects sublime, because they raise the forces of        
the soul above the height of vulgar commonplace, and discover within        
us a power of resistance of quite another kind, which gives us courage      
to be able to measure ourselves against the seeming omnipotence of          
nature.                                                                     
  In the immeasurableness of nature and the incompetence of our             
faculty for adopting a standard proportionate to the aesthetic              
estimation of the magnitude of its realm, we found our own limitation.      
But with this we also found in our rational faculty another                 
non-sensuous standard, one which has that infinity itself under it          
as a unit, and in comparison with which everything in nature is small,      
and so found in our minds a pre-eminence over nature even in it             
immeasurability. Now in just the same way the irresistibility of the        
might of nature forces upon us the recognition of our physical              
helplessness as beings of nature, but at the same time reveals a            
faculty of estimating ourselves as independent of nature, and               
discovers a pre-eminence above nature that is the foundation of a           
self-preservation of quite another kind from that which may be              
assailed and brought into danger by external nature. This saves             
humanity in our own person from humiliation, even though as mortal men      
we have to submit to external violence. In this way, external nature        
is not estimated in our aesthetic judgement as sublime so far as            
exciting fear, but rather because it challenges our power (one not          
of nature) to regard as small those things of which we are wont to          
be solicitous (worldly goods, health, and life), and hence to regard        
its might (to which in these matters we are no doubt subject) as            
exercising over us and our personality no such rude dominion that we        
should bow down before it, once the question becomes one of our             
highest principles and of our asserting or forsaking them. Therefore        
nature is here called sublime merely because it raises the imagination      
to a presentation of those cases in which the mind can make itself          
sensible of the appropriate sublimity of the sphere of its own              
being, even above nature.                                                   
  This estimation of ourselves loses nothing by the fact that we            
must see ourselves safe in order to feel this soul-stirring                 
delight-a fact from which it might be plausibly argued that, as             
there is no seriousness in the danger, so there is just as little           
seriousness in the sublimity of our faculty of soul. For here the           
delight only concerns the province of our faculty disclosed in such         
a case, so far as this faculty has its root in our nature;                  
notwithstanding that its development and exercise is left to ourselves      
and remains an obligation. Here indeed there is truth-no matter how         
conscious a man, when he stretches his reflection so far abroad, may        
be of his actual present helplessness.                                      
  This principle has, doubtless, the appearance of being too                
far-fetched and subtle, and so of lying beyond the reach of an              
aesthetic judgement. But observation of men proves the reverse, and         
that it may be the foundation of the commonest judgements, although         
one is not always conscious of its presence. For what is it that, even      
to the savage, is the object of the greatest admiration? It is a man        
who is undaunted, who knows no fear, and who, therefore, does not give      
way to danger, but sets manfully to work with full deliberation.            
Even where civilization has reached a high pitch, there remains this        
special reverence for the soldier; only that there is then further          
required of him that he should also exhibit all the virtues of              
peace-gentleness, sympathy, and even becoming thought for his own           
person; and for the reason that in this we recognize that his mind          
is above the threats of danger. And so, comparing the statesman and         
the general, men may argue as they please as to the pre-eminent             
respect which is due to either above the other; but the verdict of the      
aesthetic judgement is for the latter. War itself, provided it is           
conducted with order and a sacred respect for the rights of civilians,      
has something sublime about it, and gives nations that carry it on          
in such a manner a stamp of mind only the more sublime the more             
numerous the dangers to which they are exposed, and which they are          
able to meet with fortitude. On the other hand, a prolonged peace           
favours the predominance of a mere commercial spirit, and with it a         
debasing self-interest, cowardice, and effeminacy, and tends to             
degrade the character of the nation.                                        
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 70}
  So far as sublimity is predicated of might, this solution of the          
concept of it appears at variance with the fact that we are wont to         
represent God in the tempest, the storm, the earthquake, and the like,      
as presenting Himself in His wrath, but at the same time also in His        
sublimity, and yet here it would be alike folly and presumption to          
imagine a pre-eminence of our minds over the operations and, as it          
appears, even over the direction of such might. Here, instead of a          
feeling of the sublimity of our own nature, submission, prostration,        
Aristotle's remarks on Courage, in the utter helplessness seem more to      
constitute the attitude of mind befitting the manifestation of such an      
object, and to be that also more customarily associated with the            
idea of it on the occasion of a natural phenomenon of this kind. In         
religion, as a rule, prostration, adoration with bowed head, coupled        
with contrite, timorous posture and voice, seems to be the only             
becoming demeanour in presence of the Godhead, and accordingly most         
nations have assumed and still observe it. Yet this cast of mind is         
far from being intrinsically and necessarily involved in the idea of        
the sublimily of a religion and of its object. The man that is              
actually in a state of fear, finding in himself good reason to be           
so, because he is conscious of offending with his evil disposition          
against a might directed by a will at once irresistible and just, is        
far from being in the frame of mind for admiring divine greatness, for      
which a temper of calm reflection and a quite free judgement are            
required. Only when he becomes conscious of having a disposition            
that is upright and acceptable to God, do those operations of might         
serve, to stir within him the idea of the sublimity of this Being,          
so far as he recognizes the existence in himself of a sublimity of          
disposition consonant with His will, and is thus raised above the           
dread of such operations of nature, in which he no longer sees God          
pouring forth the vials of the wrath. Even humility, taking the form        
of an uncompromising judgement upon his shortcomings, which, with           
consciousness of good intentions, might readily be glossed over on the      
ground of the frailty of human nature, is a sublime temper of the mind      
voluntarily to undergo the pain of remorse as a means of more and more      
effectually eradicating its cause. In this way religion is                  
intrinsically distinguished from superstition, which latter rears in        
the mind, not reverence for the sublime, but dread and apprehension of      
the all-powerful Being to whose will terror-stricken man sees               
himself subjected, yet without according Him due honour. From this          
nothing can arise but grace-begging and vain adulation, instead of a        
religion consisting in a good life.                                         
  Sublimity, therefore, does not reside in any of the things of             
nature, but only in our own mind, in so far as we may become conscious      
of our superiority over nature within, and thus also over nature            
without us (as exerting influence upon us). Everything that provokes        
this feeling in us, including the might of nature which challenges our      
strength, is then, though improperly, called sublime, and it is only        
under presupposition of this idea within us, and in relation to it,         
that we are capable of attaining to the idea of the sublimity of            
that Being Which inspires deep respect in us, not by the mere               
display of its might in nature, but more by the faculty which is            
planted in us of estimating that might without fear, and of                 
regarding our estate as exalted above it.                                   
-                                                                           
       SS 29. Modality of the judgement on the sublime                      
                         in nature.                                         
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 75}
-                                                                           
  Beautiful nature contains countless things as to which we at once         
take every one as in their judgement concurring with our own, and as        
to which we may further expect this concurrence without facts               
finding us far astray. But in respect of our judgement upon the             
sublime in nature, we cannot so easily vouch for ready acceptance by        
others. For a far higher degree of culture, not merely of the               
aesthetic judgement, but also of the faculties of cognition which           
lie at its basis, seems to be requisite to enable us to lay down a          
judgement upon this high distinction of natural objects.                    
  The proper mental mood for a feeling of the sublime postulates the        
mind's susceptibility for ideas, since it is precisely in the               
failure of nature to attain to these- and consequently only under           
presupposition of this susceptibility and of the straining of the           
imagination to use nature as a schema for ideas- that there is              
something forbidding to sensibility, but which, for all that, has an        
attraction for us, arising from the fact of its being a dominion which      
reason exercises over sensibility with a view to extending it to the        
requirements of its own realm (the practical) and letting it look           
out beyond itself into the infinite, which for it is an abyss. In           
fact, without the development of moral ideas, that which, thanks to         
preparatory culture, we call sublime, merely strikes the untutored man      
as terrifying. He will see in the evidences which the ravages of            
nature give of her dominion, and in the vast scale of her might,            
compared with which his own is diminished to insignificance, only           
the misery, peril, and distress that would compass the man who was          
thrown to its mercy. So the simpleminded, and, for the most part,           
intelligent, Savoyard peasant, (as Herr von Sassure relates),               
unhesitatingly called all lovers of snow mountains fools. And who           
can tell whether he would have been so wide of the mark, if that            
student of nature had taken the risk of the dangers to which he             
exposed himself merely, as most travellers do, for a fad, or so as          
some day to be able to give a thrilling account of his adventures? But      
the mind of Sassure was bent on the instruction of mankind, and             
soul-stirring sensations that excellent man indeed had, and the reader      
of his travels got them thrown into the bargain.                            
  But the fact that culture is requisite for the judgement upon the         
sublime in nature (more than for that upon the beautiful) does not          
involve its being an original product of culture and something              
introduced in a more or less conventional way into society. Rather          
is it in human nature that its foundations are laid, and, in fact,          
in that which, at once with common understanding, we may expect             
every one to possess and may require of him, namely, a native capacity      
for the feeling for (practical) ideas, i.e., for moral feeling.             
  This, now, is the foundation of the necessity of that agreement           
between other men's judgements upon the sublime and our own, which          
we make our own imply. For just as we taunt a man who is quite              
inappreciative when forming an estimate of an object of nature in           
which we see beauty, with want of taste, so we say of a man who             
remains unaffected in the presence of what we consider sublime, that        
he has no feeling. But we demand both taste and feeling of every            
man, and, granted some degree of culture, we give him credit for both.      
Still, we do so with this difference: that, in the, case of the             
former, since judgement there refers the imagination merely to the          
understanding, as a the faculty of concepts, we make the requirement        
as a matter of course, whereas in the case of the latter, since here        
the judgement refers the imagination to reason, as a faculty of ideas,      
we do so only under a subjective presupposition (which, however, we         
believe we are warranted in making), namely, that of the moral feeling      
in man. And, on this assumption, we attribute necessity to the              
latter aesthetic judgement also.                                            
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 80}
  In this modality of aesthetic judgements, namely, their assumed           
necessity, lies what is for the Critique of judgement a moment of           
capital importance. For this is exactly what makes an a priori              
principle apparent in their case, and lifts them out of the sphere          
of empirical psychology, in which otherwise they would remain buried        
amid the feelings of gratification and pain (only with the senseless        
epithet of finer feeling), so as to place them, and, thanks to them,        
to place the faculty of judgement itself, in the class of judgements        
of which the basis of an a priori principle is the distinguishing           
feature, and, thus distinguished, to introduce them into                    
transcendental philosophy.                                                  
-                                                                           
           General Remark upon the Exposition of                            
              Aesthetic Reflective Judgements.                              
-                                                                           
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 85}
  In relation to the feeling of pleasure an object is to be counted         
either as agreeable, or beautiful, or sublime, or good (absolutely),        
(incundum, pulchrum, sublime, honestum).                                    
  As the motive of desires the agreeable is invariably of one and           
the same kind, no matter what its source or how specifically different      
the representation (of sense and sensation objectively considered).         
Hence in estimating its influence upon the mind, the multitude of           
its charms (simultaneous or successive) is alone revelant, and so           
only, as it were, the mass of the agreeable sensation, and it is            
only by the quantity, therefore, that this can be made intelligible.        
Further it in no way conduces to our culture, but belongs only to mere      
enjoyment. The beautiful, on the other hand, requires the                   
representation of a certain quality of the object, that pern-fits also      
of being understood and reduced to concepts (although in the aesthetic      
judgement it is not reduced), and it cultivates, as it instructs us to      
attend to, finality in the feeling of pleasure. The sublime consists        
merely in the relation exhibited by the estimate of the serviceability      
of the sensible in the representation of nature for a possible              
supersensible employment. The absolutely good, estimated                    
subjectively according to the feeling it inspires (the object of the        
moral feeling), as the determinability of the powers of the subject by      
means of the representation of an absolutely necessitating law, is          
principally distinguished, by the modality of a necessity resting upon      
concepts a priori, and involving not a mere claim, but a command            
upon every one to assent, and belongs intrinsically not to the              
aesthetic, but to the pure intellectual judgement. Further, it is           
not ascribed to nature but to freedom, and that in a determinant and        
not a merely reflective judgement. But the determinability of the           
subject by means of this idea, and, what is more, that of a subject         
which can be sensible, in the way of a modification of its state, to        
hindrances on the part of sensibility, while, at the same time, it can      
by surmounting them feel superiority over them-a determinability, in        
other words, as moral feeling-is still so allied to aesthetic               
judgement and its formal conditions as to be capable of being               
pressed into the service of the aesthetic representation of the             
conformity to law of action from duty, i.e., of the representation          
of this as sublime, or even as beautiful, without forfeiting its            
purity-an impossible result were one to make it naturally bound up          
with the feeling of the agreeable.                                          
  The net result to be extracted from the exposition so far given of        
both kinds of aesthetic judgements may be summed up in the following        
brief definitions:                                                          
  The beautiful is what pleases in the mere estimate formed of it           
(consequently not by intervention of any feeling of sense in                
accordance with a concept of the understanding). From this it               
follows at once that it must please apart from all interest.                
  The sublime is what pleases immediately by reason of its                  
opposition to the interest of sense.                                        
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 90}
  Both, as definitions of aesthetic universally valid estimates,            
have reference to subjective grounds. In the one case the reference is      
to grounds of sensibility, in so far as these are final on behalf of        
the contemplative understanding, in the other case in so far as, in         
their opposition to sensibility, they are, on the contrary, final in        
reference to the ends of practical reason. Both, however, as united in      
the same subject, are final in reference to the moral feeling. The          
beautiful prepares us to love something, even nature, apart from any        
interest: the sublime to esteem something highly even in opposition to      
our (sensible) interest object,                                             
  The sublime may be described in this way: It is an object (of             
nature) the representation of which determines the mind to regard           
the elevation of nature beyond our reach as equivalent to a                 
presentation of ideas.                                                      
  In a literal sense and according to their logical import, ideas           
cannot be presented. But if we enlarge our empirical faculty of             
representation (mathematical or dynamical) with a view to the               
intuition of nature, reason inevitably steps forward, as the faculty        
concerned with the independence of the absolute totality, and calls         
forth the effort of the mind, unavailing though it be, to make              
representation of sense adequate to this totality. This effort, and         
the feeling of the unattainability of the idea by means of                  
imagination, is itself a presentation of the subjective finality of         
our mind in the employment of the imagination in the interests of           
the mind's supersensible province, and compels us subjectively to           
think nature itself in its totality as a presentation of something          
supersensible, without our being able to effectuate this                    
presentation objectively.                                                   
  For we readily see that nature in space and time falls entirely           
short of the unconditioned, consequently also of the absolutely great,      
which still the commonest reason demands. And by this we are also           
reminded that we have only to do with nature as phenomenon, and that        
this itself must be regarded as the mere presentation of a                  
nature-in-itself (which exists in the idea of reason). But this idea        
of the supersensible, which no doubt we cannot further determine so         
that we cannot cognize nature as its presentation, but only think it        
as such-is awakened in us by an object the aesthetic estimating of          
which strains the imagination to its utmost, whether in respect of its      
extension (mathematical), or of its might over the mind (dynamical).        
For it is founded upon the feeling of a sphere of the mind which            
altogether exceeds the realm of nature (i.e., upon the moral feeling),      
with regard to which the representation of the object is estimated          
as subjectively final.                                                      
  As a matter of fact, a feeling for the sublime in nature is hardly        
thinkable unless in association with an attitude of mind resembling         
the moral. And though, like that feeling, the immediate pleasure in         
the beautiful in nature presupposes and cultivates a certain                
liberality of thought, i.e., makes our delight independent of any mere      
enjoyment of sense, still it represents freedom rather as in play than      
as exercising a law-ordained function, which is the genuine                 
characteristic of human morality, where reason has to impose its            
dominion upon sensibility. There is, however, this qualification, that      
in the aesthetic judgement upon the sublime this dominion is                
represented as exercised through the imagination itself as an               
instrument of reason.                                                       
                                                    {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 95}
  Thus, too, delight in the sublime in nature is only negative              
(whereas that in the beautiful is positive): that is to say, it is a        
feeling of imagination by its own act depriving itself of its               
freedom by receiving a final determination in accordance with a law         
other than that of its empirical employment. In this way it gains an        
extension and a might greater than that which it sacrifices. But the        
ground of this is concealed from it, and in its place it feels the          
sacrifice or deprivation, as well as its cause, to which it is              
subjected. The astonishment amounting almost to terror, the awe and         
thrill of devout feeling, that takes hold of one when gazing upon           
the prospect of mountains ascending to heaven, deep ravines and             
torrents raging there, deep shadowed solitudes that invite to brooding      
melancholy, and the like-all this, when we are assured of our own           
safety, is not actual fear. Rather is it an attempt to gain access          
to it through imagination, for the purpose of feeling the might of          
this faculty in combining the movement of the mind thereby aroused          
with its serenity, and of thus being superior to internal and,              
therefore, to external, nature, so far as the latter can have any           
bearing upon our feeling of well-being. For the imagination, in             
accordance with laws of association, makes our state of contentment         
dependent upon physical conditions. But acting in accordance with           
principles of the schematism of judgement (consequently so far as it        
is subordinated to freedom), it is at the same time an instrument of        
reason and its ideas. But in this capacity it is a might enabling us        
to assert our independence as against the influences of nature, to          
degrade what is great in respect of the latter to the level of what is      
little, and thus to locate the absolutely great only in the proper          
estate of the subject. This reflection of aesthetic judgement by which      
it raises itself to the point of adequacy with reason, though               
without any determinate concept of reason, is still a representation        
of the object as subjectively final, by virtue even of the objective        
inadequacy of the imagination in its greatest extension for meeting         
the demands of reason (as the faculty of ideas).                            
  Here we have to attend generally to what has been already adverted        
to, that in the transcendental aesthetic of judgement there must be no      
question of anything but pure aesthetic judgements. Consequently            
examples are not to be selected from such beautiful, or sublime             
objects as presuppose the concept of an end. For then the finality          
would be either teleological, or based upon mere sensations of an           
object: (gratification or pain) and so, in the first case, not              
aesthetic, and, in the second, not merely formal. So, if we call the        
sight of the starry heaven sublime, we must not found our estimate          
of it upon any concepts of worlds inhabited by rational beings, with        
the bright spots, which we see filling the space above us, as their         
suns moving in orbits prescribed for them with the wisest regard to         
ends. But we must take it, just as it strikes the eye, as a broad           
and all-embracing canopy: and it is merely under such a representation      
that we may posit the sublimity which the pure aesthetic judgement          
attributes to this object. Similarly, as to the prospect of the ocean,      
we are not to regard it as we, with our minds stored with knowledge on      
a variety of matters (which, however, is not contained in the               
immediate intuition), are wont to represent it in thought, as, let          
us say, a spacious realm of aquatic creatures, or as the mighty             
reservoirs from which are drawn the vapours that fill the air with          
clouds of moisture for the good of the land, or yet as an element           
which no doubt divides continent from continent, but at the same            
time affords the means of the greatest commercial intercourse               
between them-for in this way we get nothing beyond teleological             
judgements. Instead of this we must be able to see sublimity in the         
ocean, regarding it, as the poets do, according to what the impression      
upon the eye reveals, as, let us say, in its calm a clear mirror of         
water bounded only by the heavens, or, be it disturbed, as threatening      
to overwhelm and engulf everything. The same is to be said of the           
sublime and beautiful in the human form. Here, for determining grounds      
of the judgement, we must not have recourse to concepts of ends             
subserved by all: all its and members, or allow their accordance            
with these ends to influence our aesthetic judgement (in such case          
no longer pure), although it is certainly also a also a necessary           
condition of aesthetic delight that they should not conflict. With          
these ends. Aesthetic finality is the conformity to law of judgement        
in its freedom. The delight in the object depends on the reference          
which we seek to give to the imagination, subject to the proviso            
that it is to entertain the mind in a free activity. If, on the             
other hand, something else-be it sensation or concept of the                
understanding-determines the judgement, it is then conformable to law,      
no doubt, but not an act of free judgement.                                 
  Hence to speak of intellectual beauty or sublimity is to use              
expressions which, in the first place, are not quite correct. For           
these are aesthetic modes of representation which would be entirely         
foreign to us were we merely pure intelligences (or if we even put          
ourselves in thought in the position of such). Secondly, although           
both, as objects of an intellectual (moral) delight, are compatible         
with aesthetic delight to the extent of not resting upon any interest,      
still, on the: Other hand, there is a difficulty in the way of their        
alliance with such delight, since their function is to produce an           
interest, and, on the assumption that the presentation has to accord        
with delight in the aesthetic estimate, this interest could only be         
effected by means of an interest of sense combined with it in the           
presentation. But in this way the intellectual finality would be            
violated and rendered impure.                                               
  The object of a pure and unconditioned intellectual delight is the        
moral law in the might which it exerts in us over all antecedent            
motives of the mind. Now, since it is only through sacrifices that          
this might makes itself known to us aesthetically (and this involves a      
deprivation of something -though in the interest of inner                   
freedom-whilst in turn it reveals in us an unfathomable depth of            
this supersensible faculty, the consequences of which extend beyond         
reach of the eye of sense), it follows that the delight, looked at          
from the aesthetic side (in reference to sensibility) is negative,          
i.e., opposed to this interest, but from the intellectual side,             
positive and bound up with an interest. Hence it follows that the           
intellectual and intrinsically final (moral) good, estimated                
aesthetically, instead of being represented as beautiful, must              
rather be represented as sublime, with the result that it arouses more      
a feeling of respect (which disdains charm) than of love or of the          
heart being drawn towards it-for human nature does not of its own           
proper motion accord with the good, but only by virtue of the dominion      
which reason exercises over sensibility. Conversely, that, too,             
which we call sublime in external nature, or even internal nature           
(e.g., certain affections) is only represented as a might of the            
mind enabling it to overcome this or that hindrance of sensibility          
by means of moral principles, and it is from this that it derives           
its interest.                                                               
  I must dwell while on the latter point. The idea of the good to           
which affection is superadded is enthusiasm. This state of mind             
appears to be sublime: so much so that there is a common saying that        
nothing great can be achieved without it. But now every affection*          
is blind either as to the choice of its end, or, supposing this has         
been furnished by reason, in the way it is effected for it is that          
mental movement whereby the exercise of free deliberation upon              
fundamental principles, with a view to determining oneself                  
accordingly, is rendered impossible. On this account it cannot merit        
any delight on the part of reason. Yet, from an aesthetic point of          
view, enthusiasm is sublime, because it is an effort of one's powers        
called forth by ideas which give to the mind an impetus of far              
stronger and more enduring efficacy than the stimulus afforded by           
sensible representations. But (as seems strange) even freedom from          
affection (apatheia, phlegma in significatu bono) in a mind that            
strenuously follows its unswerving principles is sublime, and that,         
too, in a manner vastly superior, because it has at the same time           
the delight of pure reason on its side. Such a stamp of mind is             
alone called noble. This expression, however, comes in time to be           
applied to things-such as buildings, a garment, literary style, the         
carriage of one's person, and the like-provided they do not so much         
excite astonishment (the affection attending the representation of          
novelty exceeding expectation) as admiration (an astonishment which         
does not cease when the novelty wears off)-and this obtains where           
ideas undesignedly and artlessly accord in their presentation with          
aesthetic delight.                                                          
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 100}
-                                                                           
  *There is a specific distinction between affections and Passions.         
Affections are related merely to feeling; passions belong to the            
faculty of desire, and are inclinations that hinder or render               
impossible all determinability of the elective will by principles.          
Affections are impetuous and irresponsible; passions are abiding and        
deliberate. Thus resentment, in the form of anger, is an affection:         
but in the form of hatred (vindictiveness) it is a passion. Under no        
circumstances can the latter be called sublime; for, while the freedom      
of the mind is, no doubt, impeded in the case of affection, in passion      
it is abrogated.                                                            
-                                                                           
  Every affection of the STRENUOUS TYPE (such, that is, as excites the      
consciousness of our power of overcoming every resistance [animus           
strenuus]) is aesthetically sublime, e.g., anger, even desperation          
(the rage of forlorn hope but not faint-hearted despair). On the other      
hand, affection of the LANGUID TYPE (which converts the very effort of      
resistance into an object of displeasure [animus languidus] has             
nothing noble about it, though it may take its rank as possessing           
beauty of the sensuous order. Hence the emotions capable of                 
attaining the strength of an affection are very diverse. We have            
spirited, and we have tender emotions. When the strength of the latter      
reaches that of an affection they can be turned to no account. The          
propensity to indulge in them is sentimentality. A sympathetic grief        
that refuses to be consoled, or one that has to do with imaginary           
misfortune to which we deliberately give way so far as to allow our         
fancy to delude us into thinking it actual fact, indicates and goes to      
make a tender, but at the same time weak, soul, which shows a               
beautiful side, and may no doubt be called fanciful, but never              
enthusiastic. Romances, maudlin dramas, shallow homilies, which trifle      
with so-called (though falsely so) noble sentiments, but in fact            
make the heart enervated, insensitive to the stem precepts of duty,         
and incapable of respect for the worth of humanity in our own person        
and the rights of men (which is something quite other than their            
happiness), and in general incapable of all firm principles; even a         
religious discourse which recommends a cringing and abject                  
grace-begging and favour-seeking, abandoning all reliance on our own        
ability to resist the evil within us, in place of the vigorous              
resolution to try to get the better of our inclinations by means of         
those powers which, miserable sinners though we be, are still left          
to us; that false humility by which self-abasement, whining                 
hypocritical repentance and a merely passive frame of mind are set          
down as the method by which alone we can become acceptable to the           
Supreme Being-these have neither lot nor fellowship with what may be        
reckoned to belong to beauty, not to speak of sublimity, of mental          
temperament.                                                                
  But even impetuous movements of the mind be they allied under the         
name of edification with ideas of religion, or, as pertaining merely        
to culture, with ideas involving a social interest no matter what           
tension of the imagination they may produce, can in no way lay claim        
to the honour of a sublime presentation, if they do not leave behind        
them a temper of mind which, though it be only indirectly, has an           
influence upon the consciousness of the mind's strength and                 
resoluteness in respect of that which carries with it pure                  
intellectual finality (the supersensible). For, in the absence of           
this, all these emotions belong only to motion, which we welcome in         
the interests of good health. The agreeable lassitude that follows          
upon being stirred up in that way by the play of the affections, is         
a fruition of the state of well-being arising from the restoration          
of the equilibrium of the various vital forces within us. This, in the      
last resort, comes to no more than what the Eastern voluptuaries            
find so soothing when they get their bodies massaged, and all their         
muscles and joints softly pressed and bent; only that in the first          
case the principle that occasions the movement is chiefly internal,         
whereas here it is entirely external. Thus, many a man believes             
himself edified by a sermon in which there is no establishment of           
anything (no system of good maxims); or thinks himself improved by a        
tragedy, when he is merely glad at having got well rid of the               
feeling of being bored. Thus the sublime must in every case have            
reference to our way of thinking, i.e., to maxims directed to giving        
the intellectual side of our nature and the ideas of reason                 
supremacy over sensibility.                                                 
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 105}
  We have no reason to fear that the feeling of the sublime will            
suffer from an abstract mode of presentation like this, which is            
altogether negative as to what is sensuous. For though the                  
imagination, no doubt, finds nothing beyond the sensible world to           
which it can lay hold, still this thrusting aside of the sensible           
barriers gives it a feeling of being unbounded; and that removal is         
thus a presentation of the infinite. As such it can never be                
anything more than a negative presentation-but still it expands the         
soul. Perhaps there is no more sublime passage in the Jewish Law            
than the commandment: "Thou shalt not make unto thee any graven image,      
or any likeness of any thing that is in heaven or on earth, or under        
the earth, etc." This commandment can alone explain the enthusiasm          
which the Jewish people, in their moral period, felt for their              
religion when comparing themselves with others, or the pride                
inspired by Mohammedanism. The very same holds good of our                  
representation of the moral law and of our native capacity for              
morality. The fear that, if we divest this representation of                
everything that can commend it to the senses, it will thereupon be          
attended only with a cold and lifeless approbation and not with any         
moving force or emotion, is wholly unwarranted. The very reverse is         
the truth. For when nothing any longer meets the eye of sense, and the      
unmistakable and ineffaceable idea of morality is left in possession        
of the field, there would be need rather of tempering the ardour of an      
unbounded imagination to prevent it rising to enthusiasm, than of           
seeking to lend these ideas the aid of images and childish devices for      
fear of their being wanting in potency. For this reason, governments        
have gladly let religion be fully equipped with these accessories,          
seeking in this way to relieve their subjects of the exertion, but          
to deprive them, at the same time, of the ability, required for             
expanding their spiritual powers beyond the limits arbitrarily laid         
down for them, and which facilitate their being treated as though they      
were merely passive.                                                        
  This pure, elevating, merely negative presentation of morality            
involves, on the other hand, no fear of fanaticism, which is a              
delusion that would will some VISION beyond all the bounds of               
sensibility; i.e., would dream according to principles (rational            
raving). The safeguard is the purely negative character of the              
presentation. For the inscrutability of the idea of freedom                 
precludes all positive presentation. The moral law, however, is a           
sufficient and original source of determination within us: so it            
does not for a moment permit us to cast about for a ground of               
determination external to itself. If enthusiasm is comparable to            
delirium, fanaticism may be compared to mania. Of these, the latter is      
least of all compatible with the sublime, for it is profoundly              
ridiculous. In enthusiasm, as an affection, the imagination is              
unbridled; in fanaticism, as a deep-seated, brooding passion, it is         
anomalous. The first is a transitory accident to which the                  
healthiest understanding is liable to become at times the victim;           
the second is an undermining disease.                                       
  Simplicity (artless finality) is, as it were, the style adopted by        
nature in the sublime. It is also that of morality. The latter is a         
second (supersensible) nature, whose laws alone we know, without being      
able to attain to an intuition of the supersensible faculty within          
us-that which contains the ground of this legislation.                      
  One further remark. The delight in the sublime, no less than in           
the beautiful, by reason of its universal communicability not alone is      
plainly distinguished from other aesthetic judgements, but also from        
this same property acquires an interest in society (in which it admits      
of such communication). Yet, despite this, we have to note the fact         
that isolation from all society is looked upon as something sublime,        
provided it rests upon ideas which disregard all sensible interest. To      
be self-sufficing, and so not to stand in need of society, yet without      
being unsociable, i.e., without shunning it, is something                   
approaching the sublime-a remark applicable to all superiority to           
wants. On the other hand, to shun our fellow men from misanthropy,          
because of enmity towards them, or from anthropophobia, because we          
imagine the hand of every man is against us, is partly odious,              
partly contemptible. There is, however, a misanthropy (most improperly      
so called), the tendency towards which is to be found with advancing        
years in many right minded men, that, as far as good will goes, is          
no doubt, philanthropic enough, but as the result of long and sad           
experience, is widely removed from delight in mankind. We see               
evidences of this in the propensity to recluseness, in the fanciful         
desire for a retired country seat, or else (with the young) in the          
dream of the happiness of being able to spend one's life with a little      
family on an island unknown to the rest of the world-material of which      
novelists or writers of Robinsonades know how to make such good use.        
Falsehood, ingratitude, injustice, the puerility of the ends which          
we ourselves look upon as great and momentous, and to compass which         
man inflicts upon his brother man all imaginable evils-these all so         
contradict the idea of what men might be if they only would, and are        
so at variance with our active wish to see them better, that, to avoid      
hating where we cannot love, it seems but a slight sacrifice to forego      
all the joys of fellowship with our kind. This sadness, which is not        
directed to the evils which fate brings down upon others (a sadness         
which springs from sympathy), but to those which they inflict upon          
themselves (one which is based on antipathy in questions of                 
principle), is sublime because it is founded on ideas, whereas that         
springing from sympathy can only be accounted beautiful. Sassure,           
who was no less ingenious than profound, in the description of his          
Alpine travels remarks of Bonhomme, one of the Savoy mountains: "There      
reigns there a certain insipid sadness." He recognized, therefore,          
that, besides this, there is an interesting sadness, such as is             
inspired by the sight of some desolate place into which men might fain      
withdraw themselves so as to hear no more of the world without, and be      
no longer versed in its affairs, a place, however, which must yet           
not be so altogether inhospitable as only to afford a most miserable        
retreat for a human being. I only make this observation as a                
reminder that even melancholy, (but not dispirited sadness), may            
take its place among the vigorous affections, provided it has its root      
in moral ideas. If, however, it is grounded upon sympathy, and, as          
such, is lovable, it belongs only to the languid affections. And            
this serves to call attention to the mental temperament which in the        
first case alone is sublime are                                             
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 110}
  The transcendental exposition of aesthetic judgements now brought to      
a close may be compared with the physiological, as worked out by Burke      
and many acute men among us, so that we may see where a merely              
empirical exposition of the sublime and beautiful would bring us.           
Burke, who deserves to be called the foremost author in this method of      
treatment, deduces, on these lines, "that the feeling of the sublime        
is grounded on the impulse towards self-preservation and on fear,           
i.e., on a pain, which, since it does not go the length of disordering      
the bodily parts, calls forth movements which, as they clear the            
vessels, whether fine or gross, of a dangerous and troublesome              
encumbrance, are capable of producing delight; not pleasure but a sort      
of delightful horror, a sort of tranquility tinged With terror." The        
beautiful, which he grounds on love (from which, still, he would            
have desire kept separate), he reduces to "the relaxing, slackening,        
and enervating of the fibres of the body, and consequently a                
softening, a dissolving, a languor, and a fainting, dying, and melting      
away for pleasure." And this explanation he supports, not alone by          
instances in which the feeling of the beautiful as well as of the           
sublime is capable of being excited in us by the imagination in             
conjunction with the understanding, but even by instances when it is        
in conjunction with sensations. As psychological observations, these        
analyses of our mental phenomena are extremely fine, and supply a           
wealth of material for the favourite investigations of empirical            
anthropology. But, besides that, there is no denying the fact that all      
representations within us, no matter whether they are objectively           
merely sensible or wholly intellectual, are still subjectively              
associable with gratification or pain, however imperceptible either of      
these may be. (For these representations one and all have an influence      
on the feeling of life, and none of them, so far as it is a                 
modification of the subject, can be indifferent.) We must even admit        
that, as Epicurus maintained, gratification and pain though proceeding      
from the imagination or even from representations of the                    
understanding, are always in the last resort corporeal, since apart         
from any feeling of the bodily organ life would be merely a                 
consciousness of one's existence, and could not include any feeling of      
well-being or the reverse, i.e., of the furtherance or hindrance of         
the vital forces. For, of itself alone, the mind is all life (the           
life-principle itself), and hindrance or furtherance has to be              
sought outside it, and yet in the man himself consequently in the           
connection with his body and melting                                        
  But if we attribute the delight in the object wholly and entirely to      
the gratification which it affords through charm or emotion, then we        
must not exact from any one else agreement with the aesthetic               
judgement passed by us. For, in such matters each person rightly            
consults his own personal feeling alone. But in that case there is          
an end of all censorship of taste-unless the afforded by others as the      
result of a contingent coincidence of their judgements is to be held        
over us as commanding our assent. But this principle we would               
presumably resent, and appeal to our natural right of submitting a          
judgement to our own sense, where it rests upon the immediate               
feeling of personal well-being, instead of submitting it to that of         
others.                                                                     
  Hence if the import of the judgement of taste, where we appraise          
it as a judgement entitled to require the concurrence of every one,         
cannot be egoistic, but must necessarily, from its inner nature, be         
allowed a pluralistic validity, i.e., on account of what taste              
itself is, and not on account of the examples which others give of          
their taste, then it must found upon some a priori principle (be it         
subjective or objective), and no amount of prying into the empirical        
laws of the changes that go on within the mind can succeed in               
establishing such a principle. For these laws only yield a knowledge        
of how we do judge, but they do not give us a command as to how we          
ought to judge, and, what is more, such a command as is                     
unconditioned-and commands of this kind are presupposed by                  
judgements of taste, inasmuch as they require delight to be taken as        
immediately connected with a representation. Accordingly, though the        
empirical exposition of aesthetic judgements may be a first step            
towards accumulating the material for a higher investigation, yet a         
transcendental examination of this faculty is possible, and forms an        
essential part of the Critique of Taste. For, were not taste in             
possession of a priori principles, it could not possibly sit in             
judgement upon the judgements of others and pass sentence of                
commendation or condemnation upon them, with even the least                 
semblance of authority.                                                     
  The remaining part of the Analytic of the aesthetic judgement             
contains first of all the:                                                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 115}
            Deduction of Pure Aesthetic Judgements.                         
    SS 30. The deduction of aesthetic judgements upon objects of            
      nature must not be directed to what we call sublime in                
               nature, but only to the beautiful.                           
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 120}
  The claim of an aesthetic judgement to universal validity for             
every subject, being a judgement which must rely on some a priori           
principle, stands in need of a deduction (i.e., a derivation of its         
title). Further, where the delight or aversion turns on the form of         
the object this has to be something over and above the exposition of        
the judgement. Such is the case with judgements of taste upon the           
beautiful in nature. For there the finality has its foundation in           
the object and its outward form-although it does not signify the            
reference of this to other objects according to concepts (for the           
purpose of cognitive judgements), but is merely concerned in general        
with the apprehension of this form so far as it proves accordant in         
the mind with the faculty of concepts as well as with that of their         
presentation (which is identical with that of apprehension). With           
regard to the beautiful in nature, therefore, we may start a number of      
questions touching the cause of this finality of their forms e.g., how      
we are to explain why nature has scattered beauty abroad with so            
lavish a hand even in the depth of the ocean where it can but seldom        
be reached by the eye of man-for which alone it is. final?                  
  But the sublime in nature-if we pass upon it a pure aesthetic             
judgement unmixed with concepts of perfection, as objective                 
finality, which would make the judgement teleological-may be                
regarded as completely wanting in form or figure, and none the less be      
looked upon as an object of pure delight, and indicate a subjective         
finality of the given representation. So, now, the question suggests        
itself, whether in addition to the exposition of what is thought in an      
aesthetic judgement of this kind, we may be called upon to give a           
deduction of its claim to some (subjective) a priori principle.             
  This we may meet with the reply that the sublime in nature is             
improperly so called, and that sublimity should, in strictness, be          
attributed merely to the attitude of thought, or, rather, to that           
which serves as basis for this in human nature. The apprehension of an      
object otherwise formless and in conflict with ends supplies the            
mere occasion for our coming to a consciousness of this basis; and the      
object is in this way put to a subjectively-final use, but it is not        
estimated as subjectively-final on its own account and because of           
its form. (It is, as it were, a species finalis accepta, non data.)         
Consequently the exposition we gave of judgements upon the sublime          
in nature was at the same time their deduction. For, in our analysis        
of the reflection on the part of judgement in this case, we found that      
in such judgements there is a final relation of the cognitive               
faculties, which has to be laid a priori at the basis of the faculty        
of ends (the will), and which is therefore itself a priori final.           
This, then, at once involves the deduction, i.e., the justification of      
the claim of such a judgement to universally-necessary validity.            
  Hence we may confine our search to one for the deduction of               
judgements of taste, i.e., of judgements upon the beauty of things          
of nature, and this will satisfactorily dispose of the problem for the      
entire aesthetic faculty of judgement.                                      
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 125}
       SS 31. Of the method of the deduction of judgements                  
                          of taste.                                         
-                                                                           
  The obligation to furnish a deduction, i.e., a guarantee of the           
legitimacy of judgements of a particular kind, only arises where the        
judgement lays claim to necessity. This is the case even where it           
requires subjective universality, i.e., the concurrence of every            
one, albeit the judgement is not a cognitive judgement, but only one        
of pleasure or displeasure in a given object, i.e., an assumption of a      
subjective finality that has a thoroughgoing validity for every one,        
and which, since the judgement is one of taste, is not to be                
grounded upon any concept of the thing.                                     
  Now, in the latter case, we are not dealing with a judgement of           
cognition-neither with a theoretical one based on the concept of a          
nature in general, supplied by understanding, nor with a (pure)             
practical one based on the idea of freedom, as given a priori by            
reason-and so we are not called upon to justify a priori the                
validity of a judgement which represents either what a thing is, or         
that there is something which I ought to do in order to produce it.         
Consequently, if for judgement generally we demonstrate the                 
universal validity of a singular judgement expressing the subjective        
finality of an empirical representation of the form of an object, we        
shall do all that is needed to explain how it is possible that              
something can please in the mere formation of an estimate of it             
(without sensation or concept), and how, just as the estimate of an         
object for the sake of a cognition generally has universal rules,           
the delight of any one person may be pronounced as a rule for every         
other.                                                                      
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 130}
  Now if this universal validity is not to be based on a collection of      
votes and interrogation of others as to what sort of sensations they        
experience, but is to rest, as it were, upon an, autonomy of the            
subject passing judgement on the feeling of pleasure (in the given          
representation), i.e., upon his own taste, and yet is also not to be        
derived from concepts; then it follows that such a judgement-and            
such the judgement of taste in fact is-has a double and also logical        
peculiarity. For, first, it has universal validity a priori, yet            
without having a logical universality according to concepts, but            
only the universality of a singular judgement. Secondly, it has a           
necessity (which must invariably rest upon a priori grounds), but           
one which depends upon no a priori proofs by the representation of          
which it would be competent to enforce the assent which the                 
judgement of taste demands of every one.                                    
  The solution of these logical peculiarities, which distinguish a          
judgement of taste from all cognitive judgements, will of itself            
suffice for a deduction of this strange faculty, provided we                
abstract at the outset from all content of the judgement, viz., from        
the feeling of pleasure, and merely compare the aesthetic form with         
the form of objective judgements as prescribed by logic. We shall           
first try, with the help of examples, to illustrate and bring out           
these characteristic properties of taste.                                   
-                                                                           
       SS 32. First peculiarity of the judgement of taste.                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 135}
  The judgement of taste determines its object in respect of delight        
(as a thing of beauty) with a claim to the agreement of every one,          
just as if it were objective.                                               
  To say: "this flower is beautiful is tantamount to repeating its own      
proper claim to the delight of everyone. The agreeableness of its           
smell gives it no claim at all. One man revels in it, but it gives          
another a headache. Now what else are we to suppose from this than          
that its beauty is to be taken for a property of the flower itself          
which does not adapt itself to the diversity of heads and the               
individual senses of the multitude, but to which they must adapt            
themselves, if they are going to pass judgement upon it. And yet            
this is not the way the matter stands. For the judgement of taste           
consists precisely in a thing being called beautiful solely in respect      
of that quality in which it adapts itself to our mode of taking it in.      
  Besides, every judgement which is to show the taste of the                
individual, is required to be an independent judgement of the               
individual himself. There must be no need of groping about among other      
people's judgements and getting previous instruction from their             
delight in or aversion to the same object. Consequently his                 
judgement should be given out a priori, and not as an imitation             
relying on the general pleasure a thing gives as a matter of fact. One      
would think, however, that a judgement a priori must involve a concept      
of the object for the cognition of which it contains the principle.         
But the judgement of taste is not founded on concepts, and is in no         
way a cognition, but only an aesthetic judgement.                           
  Hence it is that a youthful poet refuses to allow himself to be           
dissuaded from the conviction that his poem is beautiful, either by         
the judgement of the public or of his friends. And even if he lends         
them an ear, he does so,-not because he has now come to a different         
judgement, but because, though the whole public, at least so far as         
his work is concerned, should have false taste, he still, in his            
desire for recognition, finds good reason to accommodate himself to         
the popular error (even against his own judgement). It is only in           
aftertime, when his judgement has been sharpened by exercise, that          
of his own free will and accord he deserts his former judgements            
behaving in just the same way as with those of his judgements which         
depend wholly upon reason. Taste lays claim simply to autonomy. To          
make the judgements of others the determining ground of one's own           
would be heteronomy.                                                        
  The fact that we recommend the works of the ancients as models,           
and rightly too, and call their authors classical, as constituting          
sort of nobility among writers that leads the way and thereby gives         
laws to the people, seems to indicate a posteriori sources of taste         
and to contradict the autonomy of taste in each individual. But we          
might just as well say that the ancient mathematicians, who, to this        
day, are looked upon as the almost indispensable models of perfect          
thoroughness and elegance in synthetic methods, prove that reason also      
is on our part only imitative, and that it is incompetent with the          
deepest intuition to produce of itself rigorous proofs by means of the      
construction of concepts. There is no employment of our powers, no          
matter how free, not even of reason itself (which must create all           
its judgements from the common a priori source), which, if each             
individual had always to start afresh with the crude equipment of           
his natural state, would not get itself involved in blundering              
attempts, did not those of others tie before it as a warning. Not that      
predecessors make those who follow in their steps mere imitators,           
but by their methods they set others upon the track of seeking in           
themselves for the principles, and so of adopting their own, often          
better, course. Even in religion-where undoubtedly every one bas to         
derive his rule of conduct from himself, seeing that he himself             
remains responsible for it and, when he goes wrong, cannot shift the        
blame upon others as teachers or leaders-general precepts learned at        
the feet either of priests or philosophers, or even drawn from ones'        
own resources, are never so efficacious as an example of virtue or          
holiness, which, historically portrayed, does not dispense with the         
autonomy of virtue drawn from the spontaneous and original idea of          
morality (a priori), or convert this into a mechanical process of           
imitation. Following which has reference to a precedent, and not            
imitation, is the proper expression for all influence which the             
products of an exemplary author may exert upon others and this means        
no more than going to the same sources for a creative work as those to      
which he went for his creations, and learning from one's predecessor        
no more than the mode of availing oneself of such sources. Taste, just      
because its judgement cannot be determined by concepts or precepts, is      
among all faculties and talents the very one that stands most in            
need of examples of what has in the course of culture maintained            
itself longest in esteem. Thus it avoids an early lapse into crudity        
and a return to the rudeness of its earliest efforts.                       
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 140}
-                                                                           
     SS 33. Second peculiarity of the judgement of taste.                   
-                                                                           
  Proofs are of no avail whatever for determining the judgement of          
taste, and in this connection matters stand just as they would were         
that judgement simply subjective.                                           
  If any one does not think a building, view, or poem beautiful, then,      
in the first place, he refuses, so far as his inmost conviction             
goes, to allow approval to be wrung from him by a hundred voices all        
lauding it to the skies. Of course he may affect to be pleased with         
it, so as not to be considered as wanting in taste. He may even             
begin to harbour doubts as to whether he has formed his taste upon          
an acquaintance with a sufficient number of objects of a particular         
kind (just as one who in the distance recognizes, as he believes,           
something as a wood which every one else regards as a town, becomes         
doubtful of the judgement of his own eyesight). But, for all that,          
he clearly perceives that the approval of others affords no valid           
proof, available for the estimate of beauty. He recognizes that             
others, perchance, may see and observe for him, and that what many          
have seen in one and the same way may, for the purpose of a                 
theoretical, and therefore logical, judgement, serve as an adequate         
ground of proof for or albeit he believes he saw otherwise, but that        
what has pleased others can never serve him as the ground of an             
aesthetic judgement. The judgement of others, where unfavourable to         
ours, may, no doubt, rightly make us suspicious in respect of our own,      
but convince us that it is wrong it never can. Hence there is no            
empirical ground of proof that can coerce any one's judgement of            
taste.                                                                      
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 145}
  In the second place, a proof a priori according to definite rules is      
still less capable of determining the judgement as to beauty. If any        
one reads me his poem, or brings me to a play, which, all said and          
done, fails to commend itself to my taste, then let him adduce Batteux      
or Lessing, or still older and more famous critics of taste, with           
all the host of rules laid down by them, as a proof of the beauty of        
his poem; let certain passages particularly displeasing to me accord        
completely with the rules of beauty (as set out by these critics and        
universally recognized): I stop my ears: I do not want to hear any          
reasons or any arguing about the matter. I would prefer to suppose          
that those rules of the critics were at fault, or at least have no          
application, than to allow my judgement to be determined by a priori        
proofs. I take my stand on the ground that my judgement is to be one        
of taste, and not one of understanding or reason.                           
  This would appear to be one of the chief reasons why this faculty of      
aesthetic judgement has been given the name of taste. For a man may         
recount to me all the ingredients of a dish, and observe of each and        
every one of them that it is just what I like, and, in addition,            
rightly commend the wholesomeness of the food; yet I am deaf to all         
these arguments. I try the dish with my own tongue and palate, and I        
pass judgement according to their verdict (not according to                 
universal principles).                                                      
  As a matter of fact, the judgement of taste is invariably laid            
down as a singular judgement upon the object. The understanding can,        
from the comparison of the object, in point of delight, with the            
judgements of others, form a universal judgement, e.g.: "All tulips         
are beautiful." But that judgement is then not one of taste, but is         
a logical judgement which converts the reference of an object to our        
taste into a predicate belonging to things of a certain kind. But it        
is only the judgement whereby I regard an individual given tulip as         
beautiful, i.e., regard my delight in it as of universal validity,          
that is a judgement of taste. Its peculiarity, however, consists in         
the fact, that, although it has merely subjective validity, still it        
extends its claims to all subjects, as unreservedly as it would if          
it were an objective judgement, resting on grounds of cognition and         
capable of being proved to demonstration.                                   
-                                                                           
     SS 34. An objective principle of taste is not possible.                
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 150}
-                                                                           
  A principle of taste would mean a fundamental premiss under the           
condition of which one might subsume the concept of an object, and          
then, by a syllogism, draw the inference that it is beautiful. That,        
however, is absolutely impossible. For I must feel the pleasure             
immediately in the representation of the object, and I cannot be            
talked into it by any grounds of proof. Thus although critics, as Hume      
says, are able to reason more plausibly than cooks, they must still         
share the same fate. For the determining ground of their judgement          
they are not able to look to the force of demonstrations, but only          
to the reflection of the subject upon his own state (of pleasure or         
displeasure), to the exclusion of precepts and rules.                       
  There is, however, a matter upon which it is competent for critics        
to exercise their subtlety, and upon which they ought to do so, so          
long as it tends to the rectification and extension of our                  
judgements of taste. But that matter is not one of exhibiting the           
determining ground of aesthetic judgements of this kind in a                
universally applicable formula-which is impossible. Rather is it the        
investigation of the faculties of cognition and their function in           
these judgements, and the illustration, by the analysis of examples,        
of their mutual subjective finality, the form of which in a given           
representation has been shown above to constitute the beauty of             
their object. Hence with regard to the representation whereby an            
object is given, the critique of taste itself is only subjective;           
viz., it is the art or science of reducing the mutual relation of           
the understanding and the imagination in the given representation           
(without reference to antecedent sensation or concept), consequently        
their accordance or discordance, to rules, and of determining them          
with regard to their conditions. It is art if it only illustrates this      
by examples; it is science if it deduces the possibility of such an         
estimate from the nature of these faculties as faculties of                 
knowledge-in general. It is only with the latter, as transcendental         
critique, that we have here any concern. Its proper scope is the            
development and justification of the subjective principle of taste, as      
an a priori principle of judgement. As an art, critique merely looks        
to the physiological (here psychological) and, consequently, empirical      
rules, according to which in actual fact taste proceeds (passing by         
the question of their possibility) and seeks to apply them in               
estimating its objects. The latter critique criticizes the products of      
fine art, just as the former does the faculty of estimating them.           
-                                                                           
      SS 35. The principle of taste is the subjective principle             
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 155}
               of the general power of judgement.                           
-                                                                           
  The judgement of taste is differentiated from logical judgement by        
the fact that, whereas the latter subsumes a representation under a         
concept of the object, the judgement of taste does not subsume under a      
concept at all-for, if it did, necessary and universal approval             
would be capable of being enforced by proofs. And yet it does bear          
this resemblance to the logical judgement, that it asserts a                
universality and necessity, not, however, according to concepts of the      
object, but a universality and necessity that are, consequently,            
merely subjective. Now the concepts in a judgement constitute its           
content (what belongs to the cognition of the object). But the              
judgement of taste is not determinable by means of concepts. Hence          
it can only have its ground in the subjective formal condition of a         
judgement in general. The subjective condition of all judgements is         
the judging faculty itself, or judgement. Employed in respect of a          
representation whereby an object is given, this requires the                
harmonious accordance of two powers of representation. These are:           
the imagination (for the intuition and the arrangement of the manifold      
of intuition), and the understanding (for the concept as a                  
representation of the unity of this arrangement). Now, since no             
concept of the object underlies the judgement here, it can consist          
only in the subsumption of the imagination itself (in the case of a         
representation whereby an object is given) under the conditions             
enabling the understanding in general to advance from the intuition to      
concepts. That is to say, since the freedom of the imagination              
consists precisely in the fact that it schematizes without a                
concept, the judgement of taste must found upon a mere sensation of         
the mutually quickening activity of the imagination in its freedom,         
and of the understanding with its conformity to law. It must therefore      
rest upon a feeling that allows the object to be estimated by the           
finality of the representation (by which an object is given) for the        
furtherance of the cognitive faculties in their free play. Taste,           
then, as a subjective power of judgement, contains a principle of           
subsumption, not of intuitions under concepts, but of the faculty of        
intuitions or presentations, i.e., of the imagination, under the            
faculty of concepts, i.e., the understanding, so far as the former          
in its freedom accords with the latter in its conformity to law.            
  For the discovery of this title by means of a deduction of                
judgements of taste, we can only avail ourselves of the guidance of         
the formal peculiarities of judgements of this kind, and                    
consequently the mere consideration of their logical form.                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 160}
   SS 36. The problem of a deduction of judgements of taste.                
-                                                                           
  To form a cognitive judgement we may immediately connect with the         
perception of an object the concept of an object in general, the            
empirical predicates of which are contained in that perception. In          
this way, a judgement of experience is produced. Now this judgement         
rests on the foundation of a priori concepts of the synthetical             
unity of the manifold of intuition, enabling it to be thought as the        
determination of an object. These concepts (the categories) call for a      
deduction, and such was supplied in the Critique of Pure Reason.            
That deduction enabled us to solve the problem: How are synthetical         
a priori cognitive judgements possible? This problem had, accordingly,      
to do with the a priori principles of pure understanding and its            
theoretical judgements.                                                     
  But we may also immediately connect with a perception a feeling of        
pleasure (or displeasure) and a delight, attending the                      
representation of the object and serving it instead of a predicate. In      
this way there arises a judgement which is aesthetic and not                
cognitive. Now, if such a judgement is not merely one of sensation,         
but a formal judgement of reflection that exacts this delight from          
everyone as necessary, something must lie at its basis as its a priori      
principle. This principle may, indeed, be a mere subjective one             
(supposing an objective one should be impossible for judgements of          
this kind), but, even as such, it requires a deduction to make it           
intelligible how an aesthetic judgement can lay claim to necessity.         
That, now, is what lies at the bottom of the problem upon which we are      
at present engaged, i.e.: How are judgements of taste possible? This        
problem, therefore, is concerned with the a priori principles of            
pure judgement in aesthetic judgements, i.e., not those in which (as        
in theoretical judgements) it has merely to subsume under objective         
concepts of understanding, and in which it comes under a law, but           
rather those in which it is itself, subjectively, object as well as         
law.                                                                        
  We may also put the problem in this way: How a judgement possible         
which, going merely upon the individual's own feeling of pleasure in        
an object independent of the concept of it, estimates this as a             
pleasure attached to the representation of the same object in every         
other individual, and does so a priori, i.e., without being allowed to      
wait and see if other people will be of the same mind?                      
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 165}
  It is easy to see that judgements of taste are synthetic, for they        
go beyond the concept and even the intuition of the object, and join        
as predicate to that intuition something which is not even a cognition      
at all, namely, the feeling of pleasure (or displeasure). But,              
although the predicate (the personal pleasure that is connected with        
the representation) is empirical, still we need not go further than         
what is involved in the expressions of their claim to see that, so far      
as concerns the agreement required of everyone, they are a priori           
judgements, or mean to pass for such. This problem of the Critique          
of judgement, therefore, is part of the general problem of                  
transcendental philosophy: How are synthetic a priori judgements            
possible?                                                                   
-                                                                           
    SS 37. What exactly it is that is asserted a priori of an               
                 object in a judgement of taste.                            
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 170}
  The immediate synthesis of the representation of an object with           
pleasure can only be a matter of internal perception, and, were             
nothing more than this sought to be indicated, would only yield a mere      
empirical judgement. For with no representation can I a priori connect      
a determinate feeling (of pleasure or displeasure) except where I rely      
upon the basis of an a priori principle in reason determining the           
will. The truth is that the pleasure (in the moral feeling) is the          
consequence of the determination of the will by the principle. It           
cannot, therefore, be compared with the pleasure in taste. For it           
requires a determinate concept of a law: whereas the pleasure in taste      
has to be connected immediately with the sample estimate prior to           
any concept. For the same reason, also, all judgements of taste are         
singular judgements, for they unite their predicate of delight, not to      
a concept, but to a given singular empirical representation.                
  Hence, in a judgement of taste, what is represented a priori as a         
universal rule for the judgement and as valid for everyone, is not the      
pleasure but the universal validity of this pleasure perceived, as          
it is, to be combined in the mind with the mere estimate of an object.      
A judgement to the effect that it is with pleasure that I perceive and      
estimate some object is an empirical judgement. But if it asserts that      
I think the object beautiful, i.e., that I may attribute that               
delight to everyone as necessary, it is then an a priori judgement.         
-                                                                           
          SS 38. Deduction of judgements of taste.                          
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 175}
  Admitting that in a pure judgement of taste the delight in the            
object is connected with the mere estimate of its form, then what we        
feel to be associated in the mind with the representation of the            
object is nothing else than its subjective finality for judgement.          
Since, now, in respect of the formal rules of estimating, apart from        
all matter (whether sensation or concept), judgement can only be            
directed to the subjective conditions of its employment in general          
(which is not restricted to the particular mode of sense nor to a           
particular concept of the understanding), and so can only be                
directed to that subjective factor which we may presuppose in all           
men (as requisite for a possible experience generally), it follows          
that the accordance of a representation with these conditions of the        
judgement must admit of being assumed valid a priori for every one. In      
other words, we are warranted in exacting from every one the                
pleasure or subjective finality of the representation in respect of         
the relation of the cognitive faculties engaged in the estimate of a        
sensible object in general*.                                                
-                                                                           
  *In order to be justified in claiming universal agreement an              
aesthetic judgement merely resting on subjective grounds, it is             
sufficient to assume: (1) that the subjective conditions of this            
faculty of aesthetic judgement are identical with all men in what           
concerns the relation of the cognitive faculties, there brought into        
action, with a view to a cognition in general. This must be true, as        
otherwise men would be incapable of communicating their                     
representations or even their knowledge; (2) that the judgement has         
paid regard merely to this relation (consequently merely to the formal      
condition of the faculty of judgement), and is pure, i.e., is free          
from confusion either with concepts of the object or sensations as          
determining grounds. If any mistake is made in this latter point, this      
only touches the incorrect application to a particular case of the          
right which a law gives us, and does not do away with the right             
generally.                                                                  
-                                                                           
                         Remark.                                            
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 180}
-                                                                           
  What makes this deduction so easy is that it is spared the necessity      
of having to justify the objective reality of a concept. For beauty is      
not a concept of the object, and the judgement of taste is not a            
cognitive judgement. All that it holds out for is that we are               
justified in presupposing that the same subjective conditions of            
judgement which we find in ourselves are universally present in             
every man, and further that we have rightly subsumed the given              
object under these conditions. The latter, no doubt, has to face            
unavoidable difficulties which do not affect the logical judgement.         
(For there the subsumption is under concepts; whereas in the aesthetic      
judgement it is under a mere sensible relation of the imagination           
and understanding mutually harmonizing with one another in the              
represented form of the object, in which case the subsumption may           
easily prove fallacious.) But this in no way detracts from the              
legitimacy of the claim of the judgement to count upon universal            
agreement-a claim which amounts to no more than this: the                   
correctness of the principle of judging validly for every one upon          
subjective grounds. For as to the difficulty and uncertainty                
concerning the correctness of the subsumption under that principle, it      
no more casts a doubt upon the legitimacy of the claim to this              
validity on the part of an aesthetic judgement generally, or,               
therefore, upon the principle itself, than the mistakes (though. not        
so often or easily incurred), to which the subsumption of the               
logical judgement under its principle is similarly liable, can              
render the latter principle, which is objective, open to doubt. But if      
the question were: How is it possible to assume a priori that nature        
is a complex of objects of taste? the problem would then have               
reference to teleology, because it would have to be regarded as an end      
of nature belonging essentially to its concept that it should               
exhibit forms that are final for our judgement. But the correctness of      
this assumption may still be seriously questioned, while the actual         
existence of beauties of nature is patent to experience.                    
-                                                                           
       SS 39. The communicability of a sensation.                           
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 185}
  Sensation, as the real in perception, where referred to knowledge,        
is called organic sensation and its specific quality may be                 
represented as completely communicable to others in a like mode,            
provided we assume that every one has a like sense to our own. This,        
however, is an absolutely inadmissible presupposition in the case of        
an organic sensation. Thus a person who is without a sense of smell         
cannot have a sensation of this kind communicated to him, and, even if      
be does not suffer from this deficiency, we still cannot be certain         
that he gets precisely the same sensation from a flower that we get         
from it. But still more divergent must we consider men to be in             
respect of the agreeableness or disagreeableness derived from the           
sensation of one and the same object of sense, and it is absolutely         
out of the question to require that pleasure in such objects should be      
acknowledged by every one. Pleasure of this kind, since it enters into      
the mind through sense-our role, therefore, being a passive one-may be      
called the pleasure of enjoyment.                                           
  On the other hand, delight in an action on the score of its moral         
character is not a pleasure of enjoyment, but one of self-asserting         
activity and in this coming up to the idea of what it is meant to           
be. But this feeling, which is called the moral feeling, requires           
concepts and is the presentation of a finality, not free, but               
according to law. It, therefore, admits of communication only               
through the instrumentality of reason and, if the pleasure is to be of      
the same kind for everyone, by means of very determinate practical          
concepts of reason.                                                         
  The pleasure in the sublime in nature, as one of rationalizing            
contemplation, lays claim also to universal participation, but still        
it presupposes another feeling, that, namely, of our supersensible          
sphere, which feeling, however obscure it may be, has a moral               
foundation. But there is absolutely no authority for my presupposing        
that others will pay attention to this and take a delight in beholding      
the uncouth dimensions of nature (one that in truth cannot be ascribed      
to its aspect, which is terrifying rather than otherwise).                  
Nevertheless, having regard to the fact that attention ought to be          
paid upon every appropriate occasion to this moral birthright, we           
may still demand that delight from everyone; but we can do so only          
through the moral law, which, in its turn, rests upon concepts of           
reason.                                                                     
  The pleasure in the beautiful is, on the other hand, neither a            
pleasure of enjoyment nor of an activity according to law, nor yet one      
of a rationalizing contemplation according to ideas, but rather of          
mere reflection. Without any guiding-line of end or principle, this         
pleasure attends the ordinary apprehension of an object by means of         
the imagination, as the faculty of intuition, but with a reference          
to the understanding as faculty of concepts, and through the operation      
of a process of judgement which bas also to be invoked in order to          
obtain the commonest experience. In the latter case, however, its           
functions are directed to perceiving an empirical objective concept,        
whereas in the former (in the aesthetic mode of estimating) merely          
to perceiving the adequacy of the representation for engaging both          
faculties of knowledge in their freedom in an harmonious (subjectively      
final) employment, i.e., to feeling with pleasure the subjective            
bearings of the representation. This pleasure must of necessity depend      
for every one upon the same conditions, seeing that they are the            
subjective conditions of the possibility of a cognition in general,         
and the proportion of these cognitive faculties which is requisite for      
taste is requisite also for ordinary sound understanding, the presence      
of which we are entitled to presuppose in every one. And, for this          
reason also, one who judges with taste (provided he does not make a         
mistake as to this consciousness, and does not take the matter for the      
form, or charm for beauty) can impute the subjective finality, i.e.,        
his delight in the object, to everyone else and suppose his feeling         
universally communicable, and that, too, without the mediation of           
concepts.                                                                   
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 190}
          SS 40. Taste as a kind of sensus communis.                        
-                                                                           
  The name of sense is often given to judgement where what attracts         
attention is not so much its reflective act as merely its result. So        
we speak of a sense of truth, of a sense of propriety, or of                
justice, etc. And yet, of course, we know, or at least ought well           
enough to know, that a sense cannot be the true abode of these              
concepts, not to speak of its being competent, even in the slightest        
degree, to pronounce universal rules. On the contrary, we recognize         
that a representation of this kind, be it of truth, propriety, beauty,      
or justice, could never enter our thoughts were we not able to raise        
ourselves above the level of the senses to that of higher faculties of      
cognition. Common human understanding which as mere sound (not yet          
cultivated) understanding, is looked upon as the least we can expect        
from any one claiming the name of man, has therefore the doubtful           
honour of having the name of common sense (sensus communis) bestowed        
upon it; and bestowed, too, in an acceptation of the word common            
(not merely in our own language, where it actually has a double             
meaning, but also in many others) which makes it amount to what is          
vulgar-what is everywhere to be met with-a quality which by no means        
confers credit or distinction upon its possessor.                           
  However, by the name sensus communis is to be understood the idea of      
a public sense, i.e., a critical faculty which in its reflective act        
takes account (a priori) of the mode of representation of everyone          
else, in order, as it were, to weigh its judgement with the collective      
reason of mankind, and thereby avoid the illusion arising from              
subjective and personal conditions which could readily be taken for         
objective, an illusion that would exert a prejudicial influence upon        
its judgement. This is accomplished by weighing the judgement, not          
so much with actual, as rather with the merely possible, judgements of      
others, and by putting ourselves in the position of everyone else,          
as the result of a mere abstraction from the limitations which              
contingently affect our own estimate. This, in turn, is effected by so      
far as possible letting go the element of matter, i.e., sensation,          
in our general state of representative activity, and confining              
attention to the formal peculiarities of our representation or general      
state of representative activity. Now it may seem that this                 
operation of reflection is too artificial to be attributed to the           
faculty which we call common sense. But this is an appearance due only      
to its expression in abstract formulae. In itself nothing is more           
natural than to abstract from charm and emotion where one is looking        
for a judgement intended to serve as a universal rule.                      
  While the following maxims of common human understanding do not           
properly come in here as constituent parts of the critique of taste,        
they may still serve to elucidate its fundamental propositions. They        
are these: (I) to think for oneself; (2) to think from the                  
standpoint of everyone else; (3) always to think consistently. The          
first is the maxim of unprejudiced thought, the second that of              
enlarged thought, the third that of consistent thought. The first is        
the maxim of a never-passive reason. To be given to such passivity,         
consequently to heteronomy of reason, is called prejudice; and the          
greatest of all prejudices is that of fancying nature not to be             
subject to rules which the understanding by virtue of its own               
essential laws lays at its basis, i.e., superstition. Emancipation          
from superstition is called enlightenment*; for although this term          
applies also to emancipation from prejudices generally, still               
superstition deserves pre-eminently (in sensu eminenti) to be called a      
prejudice. For the condition of blindness into which superstition puts      
one, which is as much as demands from one as an obligation, makes           
the need of being led by others, and consequently the passive state of      
the reason, pre-eminently conspicuous. As to the second maxim               
belonging to our habits of thought, we have quite got into the way          
of calling a man narrow (narrow, as opposed to being of enlarged mind)      
whose talents fall short of what is required for employment upon            
work of any magnitude (especially that involving intensity). But the        
question here is not one of the faculty of cognition, but of the            
mental habit of making a final use of it. This, however small the           
range and degree to which man's natural endowments extend, still            
indicates a man of enlarged mind: if he detaches himself from the           
subjective personal conditions of his judgement, which cramp the minds      
of so many others, and reflects upon his own judgement from a               
universal standpoint (which he can only determine by shifting his           
ground to the standpoint of others). The third maxim-that, namely,          
of consistent thought-is the hardest of attainment, and is only             
attainable by the union of both the former, and after constant              
attention to them has made one at home in their observance. We may          
say: The first of these is the maxim of understanding, the second that      
of judgement, the third of that reason.                                     
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 195}
-                                                                           
  *We readily see that enlightenment, while easy, no doubt, in              
thesi, in hypothesis is difficult and slow of realization. For not          
to be passive with one's reason, but always to be self-legislative, is      
doubtless quite an easy matter for a man who only desires to be             
adapted to his essential end, and does not seek to know what is beyond      
his understanding. But as the tendency in the latter direction is           
hardly avoidable, and others are always coming and promising with full      
assurance that they are able to satisfy one's curiosity, it must be         
very difficult to preserve or restore in the mind (and particularly in      
the public mind) that merely negative attitude (which constitutes           
enlightenment proper).                                                      
-                                                                           
  I resume the thread of the discussion interrupted by the above            
digression, and I say that taste can with more justice be called a          
sensus communis than can sound understanding; and that the                  
aesthetic, rather than the intellectual, judgement can bear the name        
of a public sense,* i.e., taking it that we are prepared to use the         
word sense of an effect that mere reflection has upon the mind; for         
then by sense we mean the feeling of pleasure. We might even define         
taste as the faculty of estimating what makes our feeling in a given        
representation universally communicable without the mediation of a          
concept.                                                                    
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 200}
  *Taste may be designated a sensus communis aestheticus, common human      
understanding a sensus communis logicus.                                    
-                                                                           
  The aptitude of men for communicating their thoughts requires, also,      
a relation between the imagination and the understanding, in order          
to connect intuitions with concepts, and concepts, in turn, with            
intuitions, which both unite in cognition. But there the agreement          
of both mental powers is according to law, and under the constraint of      
definite concepts. Only when the imagination in its freedom stirs           
the understanding, and the understanding apart from concepts puts           
the imagination into regular play, does the representation communicate      
itself not as thought, but as an internal feeling of a final state          
of the mind.                                                                
  Taste is, therefore, the faculty of forming an a priori estimate          
of the communicability of the feeling that, without the mediation of a      
concept, are connected with a given representation.                         
  Supposing, now, that we could assume that the mere universal              
communicability of our feeling must of itself carry with it an              
interest for us (an assumption, however, which we are not entitled          
to draw as a conclusion from the character of a merely reflective           
judgement), we should then be in a position to explain how the feeling      
in the judgement of taste comes to be exacted from everyone as a            
sort of duty.                                                               
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 205}
-                                                                           
        SS 41. The empirical interest in the beautiful.                     
-                                                                           
  Abundant proof bas been given above to show that the judgement of         
taste by which something is declared beautiful must have no interest        
as its determining ground. But it does not follow from this that,           
after it has once been posited as a pure aesthetic judgement, an            
interest cannot then enter into combination with it. This combination,      
however, can never be anything but indirect. Taste must, that is to         
say, first of all be represented in conjunction with something else,        
if the delight attending the mere reflection upon an object is to           
admit of having further conjoined with it a pleasure in the real            
existence of the object (as that wherein all interest consists). For        
the saying, a posse ad esse non valet consequentia,* which is               
applied to cognitive judgements, holds good here in the case of             
aesthetic judgements. Now this "something else" may be something            
empirical, such as an inclination proper to the nature of human             
beings, or it may be something intellectual, as a property of the will      
whereby it admits of rational determination a priori. Both of these         
involve a delight in the existence of the object, and so can lay the        
foundation for an interest in what has already pleased of itself and        
without regard to any interest whatsoever.                                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 210}
  *["From possibility to actuality."]                                       
-                                                                           
  The empirical interest in the beautiful exists only in society.           
And if we admit that the impulse to society is natural to mankind, and      
that the suitability for and the propensity towards it, i.e.,               
sociability, is a property essential to the requirements of man as a        
creature intended for society, and one, therefore, that belongs to          
humanity, it is inevitable that we should also look upon taste in           
the light of a faculty for estimating whatever enables us to                
communicate even our feeling to every one else, and hence as a means        
of promoting that upon which the natural inclination of everyone is         
set.                                                                        
  With no one to take into account but himself, a man abandoned on a        
desert island would not adorn either himself or his hut, nor would          
he look for flowers, and still less plant them, with the object of          
providing himself with personal adornments. Only in society does it         
occur to him to be not merely a man, but a man refined after the            
manner of his kind (the beginning of civilization)-for that is the          
estimate formed of one who has the bent and turn for communicating his      
pleasure to others, and who is not quite satisfied with an object           
unless his feeling of delight in it can be shared in communion with         
others. Further, a regard to universal communicability is a thing           
which every one expects and requires from every one else, just as if        
it were part of an original compact dictated by humanity itself. And        
thus, no doubt, at first only charms, e.g., colours for painting            
oneself (roucou among the Caribs and cinnabar among the Iroquois),          
or flowers, sea-shells, beautifully coloured feathers, then, in the         
course of time, also beautiful forms (as in canoes, wearing-apparel,        
etc.) which convey no gratification, i.e., delight of enjoyment,            
become of moment in society and attract a considerable interest.            
Eventually, when civilization has reached its height it makes this          
work of communication almost the main business of refined inclination,      
and the entire value of sensations is placed in the degree to which         
they permit of universal communication. At this stage, then, even           
where the pleasure which each one has in an object is but                   
insignificant and possesses of itself no conspicuous interest, still        
the idea of its universal communicability almost indefinitely augments      
its value.                                                                  
  This interest, indirectly attached to the beautiful by the                
inclination towards society, and, consequently, empirical, is,              
however, of no importance for us here. For that to which we have alone      
to look is what can have a bearing a priori, even though indirect,          
upon the judgement of taste. For, if even in this form an associated        
interest should betray itself, taste would then reveal a transition on      
the part of our critical faculty. from the enjoyment of sense to the        
moral feeling. This would not merely mean that we should be supplied        
with a more effectual guide for the final employment of taste, but          
taste would further be presented as a link in the chain' of the             
human faculties a priori upon which all legislation, depend. This much      
may certainly be said of the empirical interest in objects of taste,        
and in taste itself, that as taste thus pays homage to inclination,         
however refined, such interest will nevertheless readily fuse also          
with all inclinations and passions, which in society attain to their        
greatest variety and highest degree, and the interest in the                
beautiful, if this is made its ground, can but afford a very ambiguous      
transition from the agreeable to the good. We have reason, however, to      
inquire whether this transition may not still in some way be furthered      
by means of taste when taken in its purity.                                 
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 215}
-                                                                           
      SS 42. The intellectual interest in the beautiful.                    
-                                                                           
  It has been with the best intentions that those who love to see in        
the ultimate end of humanity, namely the morally good, the goal of all      
activities to which men are impelled by the inner bent of their             
nature, have regarded it as a mark of a good moral character to take        
an interest in the beautiful generally. But they have, not without          
reason, been contradicted, by others, who appeal to the fact of             
experience, that virtuosi in matters of taste being not alone often,        
but one might say as a general rule, vain, capricious, and addicted to      
injurious passions, could perhaps more rarely than others lay claim to      
any pre-eminent attachment to moral principles. And so it would             
seem, not only that the feeling for the beautiful is specifically           
different from the moral feeling (which as a matter of fact is the          
case), but also that the interest which we may combine with it will         
hardly consort with the moral, and certainly not on grounds of inner        
affinity.                                                                   
  Now I willingly admit that the interest in the beautiful of art           
(including under this heading the artificial use of natural beauties        
for personal adornment, and so from vanity) gives no evidence at all        
of a habit of mind attached to the morally good, or even inclined that      
way. But, on the other hand, I do maintain that to take an immediate        
interest in the beauty of nature (not merely to have taste in               
estimating it) is always a mark of a good soul; and that, where this        
interest is habitual, it is at least indicative of a temper of mind         
favourable to the moral feeling that it should readily associate            
itself with the contemplation of nature. It must, however, be borne in      
mind that I mean to refer strictly to the beautiful forms of nature,        
and to put to one side the charms which she is wont so lavishly to          
combine with them; because, though the interest in these is no doubt        
immediate, it is nevertheless empirical.                                    
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 220}
  One who alone (and without any intention of communicating his             
observations to others) regards the beautiful form of a wild flower, a      
bird, an insect, or the like, out of admiration and love of them,           
and being loath to let them escape him in nature, even at the risk          
of some misadventure to himself-so far from there being any prospect        
of advantage to him-such a one takes an immediate, and in fact              
intellectual, interest in the beauty of nature. This means that he          
is not alone pleased with nature's product in respect of its form, but      
is also pleased at its existence, and is so without any charm of sense      
having a share in the matter, or without his associating with it any        
end whatsoever.                                                             
  In this connection, however, it is of note that were we to play a         
trick on our lover of the beautiful, and plant in the ground                
artificial flowers (which can be made so as to look just like               
natural ones), and perch artfully carved birds on the branches of           
trees, and he were to find out how he had been taken in, the immediate      
interest which these things previously had for him would at once            
vanish-though, perhaps, a different interest might intervene in its         
stead, that, namely, of vanity in decorating his room with them for         
the eyes of others. The fact is that our intuition and reflection must      
have as their concomitant the thought that the beauty in question is        
nature's handiwork; and this is the sole basis of the immediate             
interest that is taken in it. Failing this, we are either left with         
a bare judgement of taste void of all interest whatever, or else            
only with one that is combined with an interest that is mediate,            
involving, namely, a reference to society; which latter affords no          
reliable indication of morally good habits of thought.                      
  The superiority which natural beauty has over that of art, even           
where it is excelled by the latter in point of form, in yet being           
alone able to awaken an immediate interest, accords with the refined        
and well-grounded habits of thought of all men who have cultivated          
their moral feeling. If a man with taste enough to judge of works of        
fine art with the greatest correctness and refinement readily quits         
the room in which he meets with those beauties that minister to vanity      
or, at least, social joys, and betakes himself to the beautiful in          
nature, so that he may there find as it were a feast for his soul in a      
train of thought which he can never completely evolve, we will then         
regard this his choice even with veneration, and give him credit for a      
beautiful soul, to which no connoisseur or art collector can lay claim      
on the score of the interest which his objects have for him. Here,          
now, are two kinds of objects which in the judgement of mere taste          
could scarcely contend with one another for a superiority. What             
then, is the distinction that makes us hold them in such different          
esteem?                                                                     
  We have a faculty of judgement which is merely aesthetic-a faculty        
of judging of forms without the aid of concepts, and of finding, in         
the mere estimate of them, a delight that we at the same time make          
into a rule for every one, without this judgement being founded on          
an interest, or yet producing one. On the other hand, we have also a        
faculty of intellectual judgement for the mere forms of practical           
maxims (so far as they are of themselves qualified for universal            
legislation)-a faculty of determining an a priori delight, which we         
make into a law for everyone, without our judgement being founded on        
any interest, though here it produces one. The pleasure or displeasure      
in the former judgement is called that of taste; the latter is              
called that of the moral feeling.                                           
  But, now, reason is further interested in ideas (for which in our         
moral feeling it brings about an immediate interest), having also           
objective reality. That is to say, it is of interest to reason that         
nature should at least show a trace or give a hint that it contains in      
itself some ground or other for assuming a uniform accordance of its        
products with our wholly disinterested delight (a delight which we          
cognize-a priori as a law for every one without being able to ground        
it upon proofs). That being so, reason must take an interest in             
every manifestation on the part of nature of some such accordance.          
Hence the mind cannot reflect on the beauty of nature without at the        
same time finding its interest engaged. But this interest is akin to        
the moral. One, then, who takes such an interest in the beautiful in        
nature can only do so in so far as he has previously set his                
interest deep in the foundations of the morally good. On these grounds      
we have reason for presuming the presence of at least the germ of a         
good moral disposition in the case of a man to whom the beauty of           
nature is a matter of immediate interest.                                   
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 225}
  It will be said that this interpretation of aesthetic judgements          
on the basis of kinship with our moral feeling has far too studied          
an appearance to be accepted as the true construction of the cypher in      
which nature speaks to us figuratively in its beautiful forms. But,         
first of all, this immediate interest in the beauty of nature is not        
in fact common. It is peculiar to those whose habits of thought are         
already trained to the good or else are eminently susceptible of            
such training; and under the circumstances the analogy in which the         
pure judgement of taste that, without relying upon any interest, gives      
us a feeling of delight, and at the same time represents it a priori        
as proper to mankind in general, stands to the moral judgement that         
does just the same from concepts, is one which, without any clear,          
subtle, and deliberate reflection, conduces to a like immediate             
interest being taken in the objects of the former judgement as in           
those of the latter-with this one difference, that the interest in the      
first case is free, while in the latter it is one founded on objective      
laws. In addition to this, there is our admiration of Nature, which in      
her beautiful products displays herself as art, not as mere matter          
of chance, but, as it were, designedly, according to a law-directed         
arrangement, and as finality apart from any end. As we never meet with      
such an end outside ourselves, we naturally look for it in                  
ourselves, and, in fact, in that which constitutes the ultimate end of      
our existence-the moral side of our being. (The inquiry into the            
ground of the possibility of such a natural finality will, however,         
first come under discussion in the Teleology.)                              
  The fact that the delight in beautiful art does not, in the pure          
judgement of taste, involve an immediate interest, as does that in          
beautiful nature, may be readily explained. For the former is either        
such an imitation of the latter as goes the length of deceiving us, in      
which case it acts upon us in the character of a natural beauty, which      
we take it to be; or else it is an intentional art obviously                
directed to our delight. In the latter case, however, the delight in        
the product would, it is true, be brought about immediately by              
taste, but there would be nothing but a mediate interest in the             
cause that lay beneath-an interest, namely, in an art only capable          
of interesting by its end, and never in itself. It will, perhaps, be        
said that this is also the case where an object of nature only              
interests by its beauty so far as a moral idea is brought into              
partnership therewith. But it is not the object that is of immediate        
interest, but rather the inherent character of the beauty qualifying        
it for such a partnership-a character, therefore, that belongs to           
the very essence of beauty.                                                 
  The charms in natural beauty, which are to be found blended, as it        
were, so frequently with beauty of form, belong either to the               
modifications of light (in colouring) or of sound (in tones). For           
these are the only sensations which permit not merely of a feeling          
of the senses, but also of reflection upon the form of these                
modifications of sense, and so embody as it were a language in which        
nature speaks to us and which has the semblance of a higher meaning.        
Thus the white colour of the lily seems to dispose the mind to ideas        
of innocence, and the other seven colours, following the series from        
the red to the violet, similarly to ideas of (1) sublimity, (2)             
courage, (3) candour, (4) amiability, (5) modesty, (6) constancy,           
(7) tenderness. The bird's song tells of joyousness and contentment         
with its existence. At least so we interpret nature-whether such be         
its purpose or not. But it is the indispensable requisite of the            
interest which we here take in beauty, that the beauty should be            
that of nature, and it vanishes completely as soon as we are conscious      
of having been deceived, and that it is only the work of art-so             
completely that even taste can then no longer find in it anything           
beautiful nor sight anything attractive. What do poets set more             
store on than the nightingale's bewitching and beautiful note, in a         
lonely thicket on a still summer evening by the soft light of the           
moon? And yet we have instances of how, where no such songster was          
to be found, a jovial host has played a trick on the guests with him        
on a visit to enjoy the country air, and has done so to their huge          
satisfaction, by biding in a thicket a rogue of a youth who (with a         
reed or rush in his mouth) knew how to reproduce this note so as to         
hit off nature to perfection. But the instant one realizes that it          
is all a fraud no one will long endure listening to this song that          
before was regarded as so attractive. And it is just the same with the      
song of any other bird. It must be nature, or be mistaken by us for         
nature, to enable us to take an immediate interest in the beautiful as      
such; and this is all the more so if we can even call upon others to        
take a similar interest. And such a demand we do in fact make, since        
we regard as coarse and low the habits of thought of those who have no      
feeling for beautiful nature (for this is the word we use for               
susceptibility to an interest in the contemplation of beautiful             
nature), and who devote themselves to the mere enjoyments of sense          
found in eating and drinking.                                               
-                                                                           
                  SS 43. Art in general.                                    
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 230}
-                                                                           
  (1.) Art is distinguished from nature as making (facere) is from          
acting or operating in general (agere), and the product or the              
result of the former is distinguished from that of the latter as            
work (opus) from operation (effectus).                                      
  By right it is only production through freedom, i.e., through an act      
of will that places reason at the basis of its action, that should          
be termed art. For, although we are pleased to call what bees               
produce (their regularly constituted cells) a work of art, we only          
do so on the strength of an analogy with art; that is to say, as            
soon as we call to mind that no rational deliberation forms the             
basis of their labour, we say at once that it is a product of their         
nature (of instinct), and it is only to their Creator that we               
ascribe it as art.                                                          
  If, as sometimes happens, in a search through a bog, we light on a        
piece of hewn wood, we do not say it is a product of nature but of          
art. Its producing cause had an end in view to which the object owes        
its form. Apart from such cases, we recognize an art in everything          
formed in such a way that its actuality must have been preceded by a        
representation of the thing in its cause (as even in the case of the        
bees), although the effect could not have been thought by the cause.        
But where anything is called absolutely a work of art, to                   
distinguish it from a natural product, then some work of man is always      
understood.                                                                 
  (2.) Art, as human skill, is distinguished also from science (as          
ability from knowledge), as a practical from a theoretical faculty, as      
technic from theory (as the art of surveying from geometry). For            
this reason, also, what one can do the' moment one only knows what          
is to be done, hence without-anything more than sufficient knowledge        
of the desired result, is not called art. To art that alone belongs         
which the possession of the most complete knowledge does not involve        
one's having then and there the skill to do it. Camper, describes very      
exactly how the best shoe must be made, but he, doubtless, was not          
able to turn one out himself.*                                              
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 235}
-                                                                           
  *In my part of the country, if you set a common man a problem like        
that of Columbus and his egg, he says, "There is no art in that, it is      
only science": i.e., you can do it if you know how; and he says just        
the same of all the would-be arts of jugglers. To that of the               
tight-rope dancer, on the other hand, he has not the least compunction      
in giving the name of art.                                                  
-                                                                           
  (3.) Art is further distinguished from handicraft. The first is           
called free, the other may be called industrial art. We look on the         
former as something which could only prove final (be a success) as          
play, i.e., an occupation which is agreeable on its own account; but        
on the second as labour, i.e., a business, which on its own account is      
disagreeable (drudgery), and is only attractive by means of what it         
results in (e.g., the pay), and which is consequently capable of being      
a compulsory imposition. Whether in the list of arts and crafts we are      
to rank watchmakers as artists, and smiths on the contrary as               
craftsmen, requires a standpoint different from that here adopted-one,      
that is to say, taking account of the proposition of the talents which      
the business undertaken in either case must necessarily involve.            
Whether, also, among the so-called seven free arts some may not have        
been included which should be reckoned as sciences, and many, too,          
that resemble handicraft, is a matter I will not discuss here. It is        
not amiss, however, to remind the reader of this: that in all free          
arts something of a compulsory character is still required, or, as          
it is called, a mechanism, without which the soul, which in art must        
be free, and which alone gives life to the work, would be bodyless and      
evanescent (e.g., in the poetic art there must be correctness and           
wealth of language, likewise prosody and metre). For not a few leaders      
of a newer school believe that the best way to promote a free art is        
to sweep away all restraint and convert it from labour into mere play.      
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 240}
                      SS 44. Fine art                                       
-                                                                           
  There is no science of the beautiful, but only a critique. Nor,           
again, is there an elegant (schone) science, but only a fine                
(schone) art. For a science of the beautiful would have to determine        
scientifically, i.e., by means of proofs, whether a thing was to be         
considered beautiful or not; and the judgement upon beauty,                 
consequently, would, if belonging to science, fail to be a judgement        
of taste. As for a beautiful science-a science which, as such, is to        
be beautiful, is a nonentity. For if, treating it as a science, we          
were to ask for reasons and proofs, we would be put off with elegant        
phrases (bons mots). What has given rise to the current expression          
elegant sciences is, doubtless, no more than this, that common              
observation has, quite accurately, noted the fact that for fine art,        
in the fulness of its perfection, a large store of science is               
required, as, for example, knowledge of ancient languages,                  
acquaintance with classical authors, history, antiquarian learning,         
etc. Hence these historical sciences, owing to the fact that they form      
the necessary preparation and groundwork for fine art, and partly also      
owing to the fact that they are taken to comprise even the knowledge        
of the products of fine art (rhetoric and poetry), have by a-confusion      
of words, actually got the name of elegant sciences.                        
  Where art, merely seeking to actualize a possible object to the           
cognition of which it is adequate, does whatever acts are required for      
that purpose. then it is mechanical. But should the feeling of              
pleasure be what it has immediately in view, it is then termed              
aesthetic art. As such it may be either agreeable or fine art. The          
description "agreeable art" applies where the end of the art is that        
the pleasure should accompany the representations considered as mere        
sensations, the description "fine art" where it is to accompany them        
considered as modes of cognition.                                           
  Agreeable arts are those which have mere enjoyment for their object.      
Such are all the charms that can gratify a dinner party:                    
entertaining narrative, the art of starting the whole table in              
unrestrained and sprightly conversation, or with jest and laughter          
inducing a certain air of gaiety. Here, as the saying goes, there           
may be much loose talk over the glasses, without a person wishing to        
be brought to book for all he utters, because it is only given out for      
the entertainment of the moment, and not as a lasting matter to be          
made the subject of reflection or repetition. (Of the same sort is          
also the art of arranging the table for enjoyment, or, at large             
banquets, the music of the orchestra-a quaint idea intended to act          
on the mind merely as an agreeable noise fostering a genial spirit,         
which, without any one paying the smallest attention to the                 
composition, promotes the free flow of conversation between guest           
and guest.) In addition must be included play of every kind which is        
attended with no further interest than that of making the time pass by      
unheeded.                                                                   
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 245}
  Fine art, on the other hand, is a mode of representation which is         
intrinsically final, and which, although devoid of an end, has the          
effect of advancing the culture of the mental powers in the                 
interests of social communication.                                          
  The universal communicability of a pleasure involves in its very          
concept that the pleasure is not one of enjoyment arising out of            
mere sensation, but must be one of reflection. Hence aesthetic art, as      
art which is beautiful, is one having for its standard the                  
reflective judgement and not organic sensation.                             
-                                                                           
     SS 45. Fine art is an art, so far as it has at the same                
             time the appearance of being nature.                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 250}
-                                                                           
   A product of fine art must be recognized to be art and not               
nature. Nevertheless the finality in its form must appear just as free      
from the constraint of arbitrary rules as if it were a product of mere      
nature. Upon this feeling of freedom in the play of our cognitive           
faculties-which play has at the same time to be final rests that            
pleasure which alone is universally communicable without being based        
on concepts. Nature proved beautiful when it wore the appearance of         
art; and art can only be termed beautiful, where we are conscious of        
its being art, while yet it has the appearance of nature.                   
  For, whether we are dealing with beauty of nature or beauty of            
art, we may make the universal statement: That is beautiful which           
pleases in the mere estimate of it (not in sensation or by means of         
a concept). Now art has always got a definite intention of producing        
something. Were this "something," however, to be mere sensation             
(something merely subjective), intended to be accompanied with              
pleasure, then such product would, in our estimation of it, only            
please through the agency of the feeling of the senses. On the other        
hand, were the intention one directed to the production of a                
definite object, then, supposing this were attained by art, the object      
would only please by means of a concept. But in both cases the art          
would please, not in the mere estimate of it, i.e., not as fine art,        
but rather as mechanical art.                                               
  Hence the finality in the product of fine art, intentional though it      
be, must not have the appearance of being intentional; i.e., fine           
art must be clothed with the aspect of nature, although we recognize        
it to be art. But the way in which a product of art seems like              
nature is by the presence of perfect exactness in the agreement with        
rules prescribing how alone the product can be what it is intended          
to be, but with an absence of laboured effect (without academic form        
betraying itself), i.e., without a trace appearing of the artist            
having always had the rule present to him and of its having fettered        
his mental powers.                                                          
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 255}
            SS 46. Fine art is the art of genius.                           
-                                                                           
  Genius is the talent (natural endowment) which gives the rule to          
art. Since talent, as an innate productive faculty of the artist,           
belongs itself to nature, we may put it this way: Genius is the innate      
mental aptitude (ingenium) through which nature gives the rule to art.      
  Whatever may be the merits of this definition, and whether it is          
merely arbitrary, or whether it is adequate or not to the concept           
usually associated with the word genius (a point which the following        
sections have to clear up), it may still be shown at the outset             
that, according to this acceptation of the word, fine arts must             
necessarily be regarded as arts of genius.                                  
  For every art presupposes rules which are laid down as the                
foundation which first enables a product, if it is to be called one of      
art, to be represented as possible. The concept of fine art,                
however, does not permit of the judgement upon the beauty of its            
product being derived from any rule that has a concept for its              
determining ground, and that depends, consequently, on a concept of         
the way in which the product is possible. Consequently fine art cannot      
of its own self excogitate the rule according to which it is to             
effectuate its product. But since, for all that, a product can never        
be called art unless there is a preceding rule, it follows that nature      
in the individual (and by virtue of the harmony of his faculties) must      
give the rule to art, i.e., fine art is only possible as a product          
of genius.                                                                  
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 260}
  From this it may be seen that genius (1) is a talent for producing        
that for which no definite rule can be given, and not an aptitude in        
the way of cleverness for what can be learned according to some             
rule; and that consequently originality must be its primary                 
property. (2) Since there may also be original nonsense, its                
products must at the same time be models, i.e., be exemplary; and,          
consequently, though not themselves derived from imitation, they            
must serve that purpose for others, i.e., as a standard or rule of          
estimating. (3) It cannot indicate scientifically how it brings             
about its product, but rather gives the rule as nature. Hence, where        
an author owes a product to his genius, he does not himself know how        
the ideas for it have entered into his head, nor has he it in his           
power to invent the like at pleasure, or methodically, and communicate      
the same to others in such precepts as would put them in a position to      
produce similar products. (Hence, presumably, our word Genie is             
derived from genius, as the peculiar guardian and guiding spirit given      
to a man at his birth, by the inspiration of which those original           
ideas were obtained.) (4) Nature prescribes the rule through genius         
not to science but to art, and this also only in so far as it is to be      
fine art.                                                                   
-                                                                           
         SS 47. Elucidation and confirmation of the above                   
                    explanation of genius.                                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 265}
  Every one is agreed on the point of the complete opposition               
between genius and the spirit of imitation. Now since learning is           
nothing but imitation, the greatest ability, or aptness as a pupil          
(capacity), is still, as such, not equivalent to genius. Even though a      
man weaves his own thoughts or fancies, instead of merely taking in         
what others have thought, and even though he go so far as to bring          
fresh gains to art and science, this does not afford a valid reason         
for calling such a man of brains, and often great brains, a genius, in      
contradistinction to one who goes by the name of shallow-pate, because      
he can never do more than merely learn and follow a lead. For what          
is accomplished in this way is something that could have been learned.      
Hence it all lies in the natural path of investigation and                  
reflection according to rules, and so is not specifically                   
distinguishable from what may be acquired as the result of industry         
backed up by imitation. So all that Newton bas set forth in his             
immortal work on the Principles of Natural Philosophy may well be           
learned, however great a mind it took to find it all out, but we            
cannot learn to write in a true poetic vein, no matter how complete         
all the precepts of the poetic art may be, or however excellent its         
models. The reason is that all the steps that Newton had to take            
from the first elements of geometry to his greatest and most                
profound discoveries were such as he could make intuitively evident         
and plain to follow, not only for himself but for every one else. On        
the other hand, no Homer or Wieland can show how his ideas, so rich at      
once in fancy and in thought, enter and assemble themselves in his          
brain, for the good reason that he does not himself know, and so            
cannot teach others. In matters of science, therefore, the greatest         
inventor differs only in degree from the most laborious imitator and        
apprentice, whereas he differs specifically from one endowed by nature      
for fine art. No disparagement, however, of those great men, to whom        
the human race is so deeply indebted, is involved in this comparison        
of them with those who on the score of their talent for fine art are        
the elect of nature. The talent for science is formed for the               
continued advances of greater perfection in knowledge, with all its         
dependent practical advantages, as also for imparting the same to           
others. Hence scientists can boast a ground of considerable                 
superiority over those who merit the honour of being called                 
geniuses, since genius reaches a point at which art must make a             
halt, as there is a limit imposed upon it which it cannot transcend.        
This limit has in all probability been long since attained. In              
addition, such skill cannot be communicated, but requires to be             
bestowed directly from the hand of nature upon each individual, and so      
with him it dies, awaiting the day when nature once again endows            
another in the same way-one who needs no more than an example to set        
the talent of which he is conscious at work on similar lines.               
  Seeing, then, that the natural endowment of art (as fine art) must        
furnish the rule, what kind of rule must this be? It cannot be one set      
down in a formula and serving as a precept-for then the judgement upon      
the beautiful would be determinable according to concepts. Rather must      
the rule be gathered from the performance, i.e., from the product,          
which others may use to put their own talent to the test, so as to let      
it serve as a model, not for imitation, but for following. The              
possibility of this is difficult to explain. The artist's ideas arouse      
like ideas on the part of his pupil, presuming nature to have               
visited him with a like proportion of the mental Powers. For this           
reason, the models of fine art are the only means of handing down this      
art to posterity. This is something which cannot be done by mere            
descriptions (especially not in the line of the arts of speech), and        
in these arts, furthermore, only those models can become classical          
of which the ancient, dead languages, preserved as learned, are the         
medium.                                                                     
  Despite the marked difference that distinguishes mechanical art,          
as an art merely depending upon industry and learning, from fine            
art, as that of genius, there is still no fine art in which                 
something mechanical, capable of being at once comprehended and             
followed in obedience to rules, and consequently something academic,        
does not constitute the essential condition of the art. For the             
thought of something as end must be present, or else its product would      
not be ascribed to an art at all, but would be a mere product of            
chance. But the effectuation of an end necessitates determinate             
rules which we cannot venture to dispense with. Now, seeing that            
originality of talent is one (though not the sole) essential factor         
that goes to make up the character of genius, shallow minds fancy that      
the best evidence they can give of their being full-blown geniuses          
is by emancipating themselves from all academic constraint of rules,        
in the belief that one cuts a finer figure on the back of an                
ill-tempered than of a trained horse. Genius can do no more than            
furnish rich material for products of fine art; its elaboration and         
its form require a talent academically trained, so that it may be           
employed in such a way as to stand the test of judgement. But, for a        
person to hold forth and pass sentence like a genius in matters that        
fall to the province of the most patient rational investigation, is         
ridiculous in the extreme.1 One is at a loss to know whether to             
laugh more at the impostor who envelops himself in such a cloud-in          
which we are given fuller scope to our imagination at the expense of        
all use of our critical faculty-or at the simple-minded public which        
imagines that its inability clearly to cognize and comprehend this          
masterpiece of penetration is due to its being invaded by new truths        
en masse, in comparison with which, detail, due to carefully weighed        
exposition and an academic examination of root principles, seems to it      
only the work of a tyro.                                                    
-                                                                           
             SS 48. The relation of genius to taste.                        
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 270}
-                                                                           
  For estimating beautiful objects, as such, what is required is            
taste; but for fine art, i.e., the production of such objects, one          
needs genius.                                                               
  If we consider genius as the talent for fine art (which the proper        
signification of the word imports), and if we would analyse it from         
this point of view into the faculties which must concur to                  
constitute such a talent, it is imperative at the outset accurately to      
determine the difference between beauty of nature, which it only            
requires taste to estimate, and beauty of art, which requires genius        
for its possibility (a possibility to which regard must also be paid        
in estimating such an object).                                              
  A beauty of nature is a beautiful thing; beauty of art is a               
beautiful representation of a thing.                                        
  To enable me to estimate a beauty of nature, as such, I do not            
need to be previously possessed of a concept of what sort of a thing        
the object is intended to be, i.e., I am not obliged to know its            
material finality (the end), but, rather, in forming an estimate of it      
apart from any knowledge of the end, the mere form pleases on its           
own account. If, however, the object is presented as a product of art,      
and is as such to be declared beautiful, then, seeing that art              
always presupposes an end in the cause (and its causality), a               
concept of what the thing is intended to be must first of all be            
laid at its basis. And, since the agreement of the manifold in a thing      
with an inner character belonging to it as its end constitutes the          
perfection of the thing, it follows that in estimating beauty of art        
the perfection of the thing must be also taken into account-a matter        
which in estimating a beauty of nature, as beautiful, is quite              
irrevelant. It is true that in forming an estimate, especially of           
animate objects of nature, e.g., of a man or a horse, objective             
finality is also commonly taken into account with a view to                 
judgement upon their beauty; but then the judgement also ceases to          
be purely aesthetic, i.e., a mere judgement of taste. Nature is no          
longer estimated as it appears like art, but rather in so far as it         
actually is art, though superhuman art; and the teleological judgement      
serves as a basis and condition of the aesthetic, and one which the         
latter must regard. In such a case, where one says, for example, "That      
is a beautiful woman," what one in fact thinks is only this, that in        
her form nature excellently portrays the ends present in the female         
figure. For one has to extend one's view beyond the mere form to a          
concept, to enable the object to be thought in such manner by means of      
an aesthetic judgement logically conditioned.                               
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 275}
  Where fine art evidences its superiority is in the beautiful              
descriptions it gives of things that in nature would be ugly or             
displeasing. The Furies, diseases, devastations of war, and the             
like, can (as evils) be very beautifully described, nay even                
represented in pictures. One kind of ugliness alone is incapable of         
being represented conformably to nature without destroying all              
aesthetic delight, and consequently artistic beauty, namely, that           
which excites disgust. For, as in this strange sensation, which             
depends purely on the imagination, the object is represented as             
insisting, as it were, upon our enjoying it, while we still set our         
face against it, the artificial representation of the object is no          
longer distinguishable from the nature of the object itself in our          
sensation, and so it cannot possibly be regarded as beautiful. The art      
of sculpture, again, since in its products art is almost confused with      
nature, has excluded from its creations the direct representation of        
ugly objects, and, instead, only sanctions, for example, the                
representation of death (in a beautiful genius), or of the warlike          
spirit (in Mars), by means of an allegory, or attributes which wear         
a pleasant guise, and so only indirectly, through an interpretation on      
the part of reason, and not for the pure aesthetic judgement.               
  So much for the beautiful representation of an object, which is           
properly only the form of the presentation of a concept and the             
means by which the latter is universally communicated. To give this         
form, however, to the product of fine art, taste merely is required.        
By this the artist, having practised and corrected his taste by a           
variety of examples from nature or art, controls his work and, after        
many, and often laborious, attempts to satisfy taste, finds the form        
which commends itself to him. Hence this form is not, as it were, a         
matter of inspiration, or of a free swing of the mental powers, but         
rather of a slow and even painful process of improvement, directed          
to making the form adequate to his thought without prejudice to the         
freedom in the play of those powers.                                        
  Taste is, however, merely a critical, not a productive faculty;           
and what conforms to it is not, merely on that account, a work of fine      
art. It may belong to useful and mechanical art, or even to science,        
as a product following definite rules which are capable of being            
learned and which must be closely followed. But the pleasing form           
imparted to the work is only the vehicle of communication and a             
mode, as it were, of execution, in respect of which one remains to a        
certain extent free, notwithstanding being otherwise tied down to a         
definite end. So we demand that table appointments, or even a moral         
dissertation, and, indeed, a sermon, must bear this form of fine            
art, yet without its appearing studied. But one would not call them on      
this account works of fine art. A poem, a musical composition, a            
picture-gallery, and so forth, would, however, be placed under this         
head; and so in a would-be work of fine art we may frequently               
recognize genius without taste, and in another taste without genius.        
-                                                                           
    SS 49. The faculties of the mind which constitute genius.               
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 280}
-                                                                           
  Of certain products which are expected, partly at least, to stand on      
the footing of fine art, we say they are soulless; and this,                
although we find nothing to censure in them as far as taste goes. A         
poem may be very pretty and elegant, but is soulless. A narrative           
has precision and method, but is soulless. A speech on some festive         
occasion may be good in substance and ornate withal, but may be             
soulless. Conversation frequently is not devoid of entertainment,           
but yet soulless. Even of a woman we may well say, she is pretty,           
affable, and refined, but soulless. Now what do we here mean by             
"soul"?                                                                     
  Soul (Geist) in an aesthetical sense, signifies the animating             
principle in the mind. But that whereby this principle animates the         
psychic substance (Seele)-the material which it employs for that            
purpose-is that which sets the mental powers into a swing that is           
final, i.e., into a play which is self-maintaining and which                
strengthens those powers for such activity.                                 
  Now my proposition is that this principle is nothing else than the        
faculty of presenting aesthetic ideas. But, by an aesthetic idea I          
mean that representation of the imagination which induces much              
thought, yet without the possibility of any definite thought whatever,      
i.e., concept, being adequate to it, and which language, consequently,      
can never get quite on level terms with or render completely                
intelligible. It is easily seen, that an aesthetic idea is the              
counterpart (pendant) of a rational idea, which, conversely, is a           
concept, to which no intuition (representation of the imagination) can      
be adequate.                                                                
  The imagination (as a productive faculty of cognition) is a powerful      
agent for creating, as it were, a second nature out of the material         
supplied to it by actual nature. It affords us entertainment where          
experience proves too commonplace; and we even use it to remodel            
experience, always following, no doubt, laws that are based on              
analogy, but still also following principles which have a higher            
seat in reason (and which are every whit as natural to us as those          
followed by the understanding in laying hold of empirical nature).          
By this means we get a sense of our freedom from the law of                 
association' (which attaches to the empirical employment of the             
imagination), with the result that the material can be borrowed by          
us from nature in accordance with that law, but be worked up by us          
into something else-namely, what surpasses nature.                          
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 285}
  Such representations of the imagination may be termed ideas. This is      
partly because they at least strain after something lying out beyond        
the confines of experience, and so seek to approximate to a                 
presentation of rational concepts (i.e., intellectual ideas), thus          
giving to these concepts the semblance of an objective reality. But,        
on the other hand, there is this most important reason, that no             
concept can be wholly adequate to them as internal intuitions. The          
poet essays the task of interpreting to sense the rational ideas of         
invisible beings, the kingdom of the blessed, hell, eternity,               
creation, etc. Or, again, as to things of which examples occur in           
experience, e.g., death, envy, and all vices, as also love, fame,           
and the like, transgressing the limits of experience he attempts            
with the aid of an imagination which emulates the display of reason in      
its attainment of a maximum, to body them forth to sense with a             
completeness. of which: nature affords no parallel; and it is in' fact      
precisely in the poetic art that the faculty of aesthetic ideas can         
show itself to full advantage. This faculty, however, regarded              
solely on its own account, is properly no more than a talent' (of           
the imagination).                                                           
  If, now, we attach to a concept a representation of the                   
imagination belonging to its presentation, but inducing solely on           
its own account such a wealth of thought as would never admit of            
comprehension in a definite concept, and, as a consequence, giving          
aesthetically an unbounded expansion to the concept itself, then the        
imagination here displays a creative activity, and it puts the faculty      
of intellectual ideas (reason) into motion-a motion, at the instance        
of a representation, towards an extension of thought, that, while           
germane, no doubt, to the concept of the object, exceeds what can be        
laid hold of in that representation or clearly expressed.                   
  Those forms which do not constitute the presentation of a given           
concept itself, but which,. as secondary representations of the             
imagination, express the derivatives connected with it, and its             
kinship with other concepts, are called (aesthetic) attributes of an        
object, the concept of Which, as an idea of reason, cannot be               
adequately presented. In this way Jupiter's eagle, with the                 
lightning in its claws, is an attribute of the mighty king of               
heaven, and the peacock of its stately queen. They do not, like             
logical (aesthetic) attributes of an object, the concept of the             
sublimity and majesty of creation, but rather something else-something      
that gives the imagination an incentive to spread its flight over a         
whole host of kindred representations that provoke more thought than        
admits of expression in a concept determined by words. They furnish an      
aesthetic idea, which serves the above rational idea as a substitute        
for logical presentation, but with the proper function, however, of         
animating the mind by opening out for it a prospect into a field of         
kindred representations stretching beyond its ken. But it is not alone      
in the arts of painting or sculpture, where the name of attribute is        
customarily employed, that fine art acts in this way; poetry and            
rhetoric also drive the soul that animates their work wholly from           
the aesthetic attributes of the objects-attributes which go hand in         
hand with the logical, and give the imagination an impetus to bring         
more thought into: play in the matter, though in an undeveloped             
manner, than allows of being brought within the embrace of a                
concept, or, therefore, of being definitely formulated in language.         
For the sake of brevity I must confine myself to a few examples             
only. When the great king expresses himself in one of his poems by          
saying:                                                                     
-                                                                           
    Oui, finissons sans trouble, et mourons sans regrets,                   
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 290}
    En laissant l'Univers comble de nos bienfaits.                          
    Ainsi l'Astre du jour, au bout de sa carriere,                          
    Repand sur l'horizon une douce lumiere,                                 
    Et les derniers rayons qu'il darde dans les airs                        
    Sont les derniers soupirs qu'il donne a l'Univers;                      
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 295}
-                                                                           
he kindles in this way his rational idea of a cosmopolitan sentiment        
even at the close of life, with help of an attribute which the              
imagination (in remembering all the pleasures of a fair summer's day        
that is over and gone-a memory of which pleasures is suggested by a         
serene evening) annexes to that representation, and which stirs up a        
crowd of sensations and secondary representations for which no              
expression can be found. On the other hand, even an intellectual            
concept may serve, conversely, as attribute for a representation of         
sense, and so animate the latter with the idea of the supersensible;        
but only by the aesthetic factor subjectively attaching to the              
consciousness of the supersensible being employed for the purpose. So,      
for example, a certain poet says in his description of a beautiful          
morning: "The sun arose, as out of virtue rises peace." The                 
consciousness of virtue, even where we put ourselves only in thought        
in the position of a virtuous man, diffuses in the mind a multitude of      
sublime and tranquillizing feelings, and gives a boundless outlook          
into a happy future, such as no expression within the compass of a          
definite concept completely attains.*                                       
-                                                                           
  *Perhaps there has never been a more sublime utterance, or a thought      
more sublimely expressed, than the well-known inscription upon the          
Temple of Isis (Mother Nature): "I am all that is, and that was, and        
that shall be, and no mortal hath raised the veil from before my            
face." Segner made use of this idea in a suggestive vignette on the         
frontispiece of his Natural Philosophy, in order to inspire his             
pupil at the threshold of that temple into which he was about to            
lead him, with such a holy awe as would dispose his mind to serious         
attention.                                                                  
-                                                                           
  In a word, the aesthetic idea is a representation of the                  
imagination, annexed to a given concept, with which, in the free            
employment of imagination, such a multiplicity of partial                   
representations are bound up, that no expression indicating a definite      
concept can be found for it one which on that account allows a concept      
to be supplemented in thought by much that is indefinable in words,         
and the feeling of which quickens the cognitive faculties, and with         
language, as a mere thing of the letter, binds up the spirit (soul)         
also.                                                                       
  The mental powers whose union in a certain relation constitutes           
genius are imagination and understanding. Now, since the                    
imagination, in its employment on behalf of cognition, is subjected to      
the constraint of the understanding and the restriction of having to        
be conformable to the concept belonging' thereto, whereas                   
aesthetically it is free to furnish of its own accord, over and             
above that agreement with the concept, a wealth of undeveloped              
material for the understanding, to which the latter paid no regard          
in its concept, but which it can make use of, not so much                   
objectively for cognition, as subjectively for quickening the               
cognitive faculties, and hence also indirectly for cognitions, it           
may be seen that genius properly consists in the happy relation, which      
science cannot teach nor industry learn, enabling one to find out           
ideas for a given concept, and, besides, to hit upon the expression         
for them-the expression by means of which the subjective mental             
condition induced by the ideas as the concomitant of a concept may          
be communicated to others. This latter talent is properly that which        
is termed soul. For to get an expression for what is indefinable in         
the mental state accompanying a particular representation and to            
make it universally communicable-be the expression in language or           
painting or statuary-is a "thing requiring a faculty for laying hold        
of the rapid and transient play of the imagination, and for unifying        
it in a concept (which for that very reason is original, and reveals a      
new rule which could not have been inferred from any preceding              
principles or examples) that admits of communication without any            
constraint of rules.                                                        
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 300}
-                                                                           
  If, after this analysis, we cast a glance back upon the above             
definition of what is called genius, we find: First, that it is a           
talent for art-not one for science, in which clearly known rules            
must take the lead and determine the procedure. Secondly, being a           
talent in the line of art, it presupposes a definite concept of the         
product-as its end. Hence it presupposes understanding, but, in             
addition, a representation, indefinite though it be, of the                 
material, i.e., of the intuition, required for the presentation of          
that concept, and so a relation of the imagination to the                   
understanding. Thirdly, it displays itself, not so much in the working      
out of the projected end in the presentation of a definite concept, as      
rather in the portrayal, or expression of aesthetic ideas containing a      
wealth of material for effecting that intention. Consequently the           
imagination is represented by it in its freedom from all guidance of        
rules, but still as final for the presentation of the given concept.        
Fourthly, and lastly, the unsought and undesigned subjective                
finality in the free harmonizing of the imagination with the                
understanding's conformity to law presupposes a proportion and              
accord between these faculties such as cannot be brought about by           
any observance of rules, whether of science or mechanical imitation,        
but can only be produced by the nature of the individual.                   
  Genius, according to these presuppositions, is the exemplary              
originality of the natural endowments of an individual in the free          
employment of his cognitive faculties. On this showing, the product of      
a genius (in respect of so much in this product as is attributable          
to genius, and not to possible learning or academic instruction) is an      
example, not for imitation (for that would mean the loss of the             
element of genius, and just the very soul of the work), but to be           
followed by another genius-one whom it arouses to a sense of his own        
originality in putting freedom from the constraint of rules so into         
force in his art that for art itself a new rule is won-which is what        
shows a talent to be exemplary. Yet, since the genius is one of             
nature's elect-a type that must be regarded as but a rare                   
phenomenon-for other clever minds his example gives rise to a               
school, that is to say a methodical instruction according to rules,         
collected, so far as the circumstances admit, from such products of         
genius and their peculiarities. And, to that extent, fine art is for        
such persons a matter of imitation, for which nature, through the           
medium of a genius gave the rule.                                           
  But this imitation becomes aping when the pupil copies everything         
down to the deformities which the genius only of necessity suffered to      
remain, because they could hardly be removed without loss of force          
to the idea. This courage has merit only in the case of a genius. A         
certain boldness of expression and, in general, many a deviation            
from the common rule becomes him well, but in no sense is it a thing        
worthy of imitation. On the contrary it remains all through                 
intrinsically a blemish, which one is bound to try to remove, but           
for which the genius is, as it were, allowed to plead a privilege,          
on the ground that a scrupulous carefulness would spoil what is             
inimitable in the impetuous ardour of his soul. Mannerism is another        
kind of aping-an aping of peculiarity (originality) in general, for         
the sake of removing oneself as far as possible from imitators,             
while the talent requisite to enable one to be at the same time             
exemplary is absent. There are, in fact, two modes (modi) in general        
of arranging one's thoughts for utterance. The one is called a              
manner (modus aestheticus), the other a method (modus logicus). The         
distinction between them is this: the former possesses no standard          
other than the feeling of unity in the presentation, whereas the            
latter here follows definite principles. As a consequence, the              
former is alone admissible for fine art. It is only, however, where         
the manner of carrying the idea into execution in a product of art          
is aimed at singularity, instead of being made appropriate to the           
idea, that mannerism is properly ascribed to such a product. The            
ostentatious (precieux), forced, and affected styles, intended to mark      
one out from the common herd (though soul is wanting), resemble the         
behaviour of a man who, as we say, hears himself talk, or who stands        
and moves about as if he were on a stage to be gaped at-action which        
invariably betrays a tyro.                                                  
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 305}
        SS 50. The combination of taste and genius in                       
                     products of fine art.                                  
-                                                                           
  To ask whether more stress should be laid in matters of fine art          
upon the presence of genius or upon that of taste, is equivalent to         
asking whether more turns upon imagination or upon judgement. Now,          
imagination rather entitles an art to be called an inspired                 
(geistreiche) than a fine art. It is only in respect of judgement that      
the name of fine art is deserved. Hence it follows that judgement,          
being the indispensable condition (conditio sine qua non), is at least      
what one must look to as of capital importance in forming an                
estimate of art as fine art. So far as beauty is concerned, to be           
fertile and original in ideas is not such an imperative requirement as      
it is that the imagination in its freedom should be in accordance with      
the understanding's conformity to law. For, in lawless freedom,             
imagination, with all its wealth, produces nothing but nonsense; the        
power of judgement, on the other hand, is the faculty that makes it         
consonant with understanding.                                               
  Taste, like judgement in general, is the discipline (or                   
corrective) of genius. It severely clips its wings, and makes it            
orderly or polished; but at the same time it gives it guidance              
directing and controlling its flight, so that it may preserve its           
character of finality. It introduces a clearness and order into the         
plenitude of thought, and in so doing gives stability to the ideas,         
and qualifies them at once for permanent and universal approval, for        
being followed by others, and for a continually progressive culture.        
And so, where the interests of both these qualities clash in a              
product, and there has to be a sacrifice of something, then it              
should rather be on the side of genius; and judgement, which in             
matters of fine art bases its decision on its own proper principles,        
will more readily endure an abatement of the freedom and wealth of the      
imagination than that the understanding should be compromised.              
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 310}
  The requisites for fine art are, therefore, imagination,                  
understanding, soul, and taste.*                                            
-                                                                           
  *The first three faculties are first brought into union by means          
of the fourth. Hume, in his history, informs the English that although      
they are second in their works to no other people in the world in           
respect the evidences they afford of the three first qualities              
separately considered, still in what unites them they must yield to         
their neighbours, the French.                                               
-                                                                           
             SS 51. The division of the fine arts.                          
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 315}
-                                                                           
  Beauty (whether it be of nature or of art) may in general be              
termed the expression of aesthetic ideas. But the provision must be         
added that with beauty of art this idea must be excited through the         
medium of a concept of the object, whereas with beauty of nature the        
bare reflection upon a given intuition, apart from any concept of what      
the object is intended to be, is sufficient for awakening and               
communicating the idea of which that object is regarded as the              
expression.                                                                 
  Accordingly, if we wish to make a division of the fine arts, we           
can choose for that purpose, tentatively at least, no more                  
convenient principle than the analogy which art bears to the mode of        
expression of which men avail themselves in speech with a view to           
communicating themselves to one another as completely as possible,          
i.e., not merely in respect of their concepts but in respect of             
their sensations also.* Such expression consists in word, gesture, and      
tone (articulation, gesticulation, and modulation). It is the               
combination of these three modes of expression which alone constitutes      
a complete communication of the speaker. For thought, intuition, and        
sensation are in this way conveyed to others simultaneously and in          
conjunction.                                                                
-                                                                           
  *The reader is not to consider this scheme for a possible division        
of the fine arts as a deliberate theory. It is only one of the various      
attempts that can and ought to be made.                                     
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 320}
-                                                                           
  Hence there are only three kinds of fine art: the art of speech,          
formative art, and the art of the play of sensations (as external           
sense impressions). This division might also be arranged as a               
dichotomy, so that fine art would be divided into that of the               
expression of thoughts or intuitions, the latter being subdivided           
according to the distinction between the form and the matter                
(sensation). It would, however, in that case appear too abstract,           
and less in line with popular concepztions.                                 
  (1) The arts of speech are rhetoric and poetry. Rhetoric is the           
art of transacting a serious business of the understanding as if it         
were a free play of the imagination; poetry that of conducting a            
free play of the imagination as if it were a serious business of the        
understanding.                                                              
  Thus the orator announces a serious business, and for the purpose of      
entertaining his audience conducts it as if it were a mere play with        
ideas. The poet promises merely an entertaining play with ideas, and        
yet for the understanding there enures as much as if the promotion          
of its business had been his one intention. The combination and             
harmony of the two faculties of cognition, sensibility and                  
understanding, which, though doubtless indispensable to one another,        
do not readily permit of being united without compulsion and                
reciprocal abatement, must have the appearance of being undesigned and      
a spontaneous occurrence-otherwise it is not fine art. For this reason      
what is studied and laboured must be here avoided. For fine art must        
be free art in a double sense: i.e., not alone in a sense opposed to        
contract work, as not being a work the magnitude of which may be            
estimated, exacted, or paid for, according to a definite standard, but      
free also in the sense that, while the mind, no doubt, occupies             
itself, still it does so without ulterior regard to any other end, and      
yet with a feeling of satisfaction and stimulation (independent of          
reward).                                                                    
  The orator, therefore, gives something which he does not promise,         
viz., an entertaining play of the imagination. On the other hand,           
there is something in which he fails to come up to his promise, and         
a thing, too, which is his avowed business, namely, the engagement          
of the understanding to some end. The poet's promise, on the contrary,      
is a modest one, and a mere play with ideas is all he holds out to us,      
but he accomplishes something worthy of being made a serious business,      
namely, the using of play to provide food for the understanding, and        
the giving of life to its concepts by means of the imagination.             
Hence the orator in reality performs less than he promises, the poet        
more.                                                                       
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 325}
  (2) The formative arts, or those for the expression of ideas in           
sensuous intuition (not by means of representations of mere                 
imagination that are excited by words) are arts either of sensuous          
truth or of sensuous semblance. The first is called plastic art, the        
second painting. Both use figures in space for the expression of            
ideas: the former makes figures discernible to two senses, sight and        
touch (though, so far as the latter sense is concerned, without regard      
to beauty), the latter makes them so to the former sense alone. The         
aesthetic idea (archetype, original) is the fundamental basis of            
both in the imagination; but the figure which constitutes its               
expression (the ectype, the copy) is given either in its bodily             
extension (the way the object itself exists) or else in accordance          
with the picture which it forms of itself in the eye (according to its      
appearance when projected on a flat surface). Or, whatever the              
archetype is, either the reference to an actual end or only the             
semblance of one may be imposed upon reflection as its condition.           
  To plastic art, as the first kind of formative fine art, belong           
sculpture and architecture. The first is that which presents                
concepts of things corporeally, as they might exist in nature               
(though as fine art it directs its attention to aesthetic finality).        
The second is the art of presenting concepts of things which are            
possible only through art, and the determining ground of whose form is      
not nature but an arbitrary end-and of presenting them both with a          
view to this purpose and yet, at the same time, with aesthetic              
finality. In architecture the chief point is a certain use of the           
artistic object to which, as the condition, the aesthetic ideas are         
limited. In sculpture the mere expression of aesthetic ideas is the         
main intention. Thus statues of men, gods, animals, etc., belong to         
sculpture; but temples, splendid buildings for public concourse, or         
even dwelling-houses, triumphal arches, columns, mausoleums, etc.,          
erected as monuments, belong to architecture, and in fact all               
household furniture (the work of cabinetmakers, and so forth-things         
meant to be used) may be added to the list, on the ground that              
adaptation of the product to a particular use is the essential element      
in a work of architecture. On the other hand, a mere piece of               
sculpture, made simply to be looked at and intended to please on its        
own account, is, as a corporeal presentation, a mere imitation of           
nature, though one in which regard is paid to aesthetic ideas, and          
in which, therefore, sensuous truth should not go the length of losing      
the appearance of being an art and a product of the elective will.          
  Painting, as the second kind of formative art, which presents the         
sensuous semblance in artful combination with ideas, I would divide         
into that of the beautiful Portrayal of nature, and that of the             
beautiful arrangement of its products. The first is painting proper,        
the second landscape gardening. For the first gives only the semblance      
of bodily extension; whereas the second, giving this, no doubt,             
according to its truth, gives only the semblance of utility and             
employment for ends other than the play of the imagination in the           
contemplation of its forms.* The latter consists in no more than            
decking out the ground with the same manifold variety (grasses,             
flowers, shrubs, and trees, and even water, hills, and dales) as            
that with which nature presents it to our view, only arranged               
differently and in obedience to certain ideas. The beautiful                
arrangement of corporeal things, however, is also a thing for the           
eye only, just like painting-the sense of touch can form no intuitable      
representation of such a form, In addition I would place under the          
head of painting, in the wide sense, the decoration of rooms by             
means of hangings, ornamental accessories, and all beautiful furniture      
the sole function of which is to be looked at; and in the same way the      
art of tasteful dressing (with rings, snuffboxes, etc.). For a              
parterre of various flowers, a room with a variety of ornaments             
(including even the ladies' attire), go to make at a festal                 
gathering a sort of picture which, like pictures in the true sense          
of the word (those which are not intended to teach history or               
natural science), has no business beyond appealing to the eye, in           
order to entertain the imagination in free play with ideas, and to          
engage actively the aesthetic judgement independently of any                
definite end. No matter how heterogeneous, on the mechanical side, may      
be the craft involved in all this decoration, and no matter what a          
variety of artists may be required, still the judgement of taste, so        
far as it is one upon what is beautiful in this art, is determined          
in one and the same way: namely, as a judgement only upon the forms         
(without regard to any end) as they present themselves to the eye,          
singly or in combination, according to their effect upon the                
imagination. The justification, however, of bringing formative art (by      
analogy) under a common head with gesture in a speech, lies in the          
fact that through these figures the soul of the artists furnishes a         
bodily expression for the substance and character of his thought,           
and makes the thing itself speak, as it were, in mimic language-a very      
common play of our fancy, that attributes to lifeless things a soul         
suitable to their form, and that uses them as its mouthpiece.               
-                                                                           
  *It seems strange that landscape gardening may be regarded as a kind      
of painting, notwithstanding that it presents its forms corporeally.        
But, as it takes its forms bodily from nature (the trees, shrubs,           
grasses, and flowers taken, originally at least, from wood and              
field) it is to that extent not an art such as, let us say, plastic         
art. Further, the arrangement which it makes is not conditioned by any      
concept of the object or of its end (as is the case in sculpture), but      
by the mere free play of the imagination in the act of                      
contemplation. Hence it bears a degree of resemblance to simple             
aesthetic painting that has no definite theme (but by means of light        
and shade makes a pleasing composition of atmosphere, land, and             
water.)                                                                     
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 330}
-                                                                           
  (3) The art of the beautiful play of sensations (sensations that          
arise from external stimulation), which is a play of sensations that        
has nevertheless to permit of universal communication, can only be          
concerned with the proportion of the different degrees of tension in        
the sense to which the sensation belongs, i.e., with its tone. In this      
comprehensive sense of the word, it may be divided into the artificial      
play of sensations of hearing and of sight, consequently into music         
and the art of colour. It is of note that these two senses, over and        
above such susceptibility for impressions as is required to obtain          
concepts of external objects by means of these impressions, also admit      
of a peculiar associated sensation of which we cannot well determine        
whether it is based on sense or reflection; and that this                   
sensibility may at times be wanting, although the sense, in other           
respects, and in what concerns its employment for the cognition of          
objects, is by no means deficient but particularly keen. In other           
words, we cannot confidently assert whether a colour or a tone (sound)      
is merely an agreeable sensation, or whether they are in themselves         
a beautiful play of sensations, and in being estimated                      
aesthetically, convey, as such, a delight in their form. If we              
consider the velocity of the vibrations of light, or, in the second         
case, of the air, which in all probability far outstrips any                
capacity on our part for forming an immediate estimate in perception        
of the time interval between them, we should be led to believe that it      
is only the effect of those vibrating movements upon the elastic parts      
of our body, that can be evident to sense, but that the                     
time-interval between them is not noticed nor involved in our               
estimate, and that, consequently, all that enters into combination          
with colours and tones is agreeableness, and not beauty, of their           
composition. But, let us consider, on the other hand, first, the            
mathematical character both of the proportion of those vibrations in        
music, and of our judgement upon it, and, as is reasonable, form an         
estimate of colour contrasts on the analogy of the latter. Secondly,        
let us consult the instances, albeit rare, of men who, with the best        
of sight, have failed to distinguish colours, and, with the sharpest        
hearing, to distinguish tones, while for men who have this ability the      
perception of an altered quality (not merely of the degree of the           
sensation) in the case of the different intensities in the scale of         
colours or tones is definite, as is also the number of those which may      
be intelligibly distinguished. Bearing all this in mind, we may feel        
compelled to look upon the sensations afforded by both, not as mere         
sense-impressions, but as the effect of an estimate of form in the          
play of a number of sensations. The difference which the one opinion        
or the other occasions in the estimate of the basis of music would,         
however, only give rise to this much change in its definition, that         
either it is to be interpreted, as we have done, as the beautiful play      
of sensations (through bearing), or else as one of agreeable                
sensations. According to the former interpretation, alone, would music      
be represented out and out as a fine art, whereas according to the          
latter it would be represented as (in part at least) an agreeable art.      
-                                                                           
       SS 52. The combination of the fine arts in one and                   
                      the same product.                                     
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 335}
-                                                                           
  Rhetoric may in a drama be combined with a pictorial presentation as      
well of its subjects as of objects; as may poetry with music in a           
song; and this again with a pictorial (theatrical) presentation in          
an opera; and so may the play of sensations in a piece of music with        
the play of figures in a dance, and so on. Even the presentation of         
the sublime, so far as it belongs to fine art, may be brought into          
union with beauty in a tragedy in verse, a didactic poem or an              
oratorio, and in this combination fine art is even more artistic.           
Whether it is also more beautiful (having regard to the multiplicity        
of different kinds of delight which cross one another) may in some          
of these instances be doubted. Still in all fine art the essential          
element consists in the form which is final for observation and for         
estimating. Here the pleasure is at the same time culture, and              
disposes the soul to ideas, making it thus susceptible of such              
pleasure and entertainment in greater abundance. The matter of              
sensation (charm or emotion) is not essential. Here the aim is              
merely enjoyment, which leaves nothing behind it in the idea, and           
renders the soul dull, the object in the course of time distasteful,        
and the mind dissatisfied with itself and ill-humoured, owing to a          
consciousness that in the judgement of reason its disposition is            
perverse.                                                                   
  Where fine arts are not, either proximately or remotely, brought          
into combination with moral ideas, which alone are attended with a          
selfsufficing delight, the above is the fate that ultimately awaits         
them. They then only serve for a diversion, of which one continually        
feels an increasing need in proportion as one has availed oneself of        
it as a means of dispelling the discontent of one's mind, with the          
result that one makes oneself ever more-and more unprofitable and           
dissatisfied with oneself. With a view to the purpose first named, the      
beauties of nature are in general the most beneficial, if one is early      
habituated to observe, estimate, and admire them.                           
-                                                                           
         SS 53. Comparative estimate of the aesthetic worth                 
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 340}
                         of the fine arts.                                  
-                                                                           
  Poetry (which owes its origin almost entirely to genius and is least      
willing to be led by precepts or example) holds the first rank among        
all the arts. It expands the mind by giving freedom to the imagination      
and by offering, from among the boundless multiplicity of possible          
forms accordant with a given concept, to whose bounds it is                 
restricted, that one which couples with the presentation of the             
concept a wealth of thought to which no verbal expression is                
completely adequate, and by thus rising aesthetically to ideas. It          
invigorates the mind by letting it feel its faculty-free, spontaneous,      
and independent of determination by nature of regarding and estimating      
nature as phenomenon in the light of aspects which nature of itself         
does not afford us in experience, either for sense or understanding,        
and of employing it accordingly in behalf of, and as a sort of              
schema for, the supersensible. It plays with semblance, which it            
produces at will, but not as an instrument of deception; for its            
avowed pursuit is merely one of play, which, however, understanding         
may turn to good account and employ for its own purpose. Rhetoric,          
so far as this is taken to mean the art of persuasion, i.e., the art        
of deluding by means of a fair semblance (as ars oratoria), and not         
merely excellence of speech (eloquence and style), is a dialectic,          
which borrows from poetry only so much as is necessary to win over          
men's minds to the side of the speaker before they have weighed the         
matter, and to rob their verdict of its freedom. Hence it can be            
recommended neither for the bar nor the pulpit. For where civil             
laws, the right of individual persons, or the permanent instruction         
and determination of men's minds to a correct knowledge and a               
conscientious observance of their duty is at stake, then it is below        
the dignity of an undertaking of such moment to exhibit even a trace        
of the exuberance of wit and imagination, and, still more, of the           
art of talking men round and prejudicing them in favour of any one.         
For although such art is capable of being at times directed to ends         
intrinsically legitimate and praiseworthy, still it becomes                 
reprehensible on account of the subjective injury done in this way          
to maxims and sentiments, even where objectively the action may be          
lawful. For it is not enough to do what is right, but we should             
practise it solely on the ground of its being right. Further, the           
simple lucid concept of human concerns of this kind, backed up with         
lively illustrations of it, exerts of itself, in the absence of any         
offence against the rules of euphony of speech or of propriety in           
the expression of ideas of reason (all which together make up               
excellence of speech), a sufficient influence upon human minds to           
obviate the necessity of having recourse here to the machinery of           
persuasion, which, being equally available for the purpose of               
putting a fine gloss or a cloak upon vice-and error, fails to rid           
one completely of the lurking suspicion that one is being artfully          
hoodwinked. In poetry everything is straight and above board. It shows      
its hand: it desires to carry on a mere entertaining play with the          
imagination, and one consonant, in respect of form, with the laws of        
understanding, and it does not seek to steal upon and ensnare the           
understanding with a sensuous presentation.*                                
-                                                                           
  *I confess to the pure delight which I have ever been afforded by         
a beautiful poem; whereas the reading of the best speech of a Roman         
forensic orator, a modern parliamentary debater, or a preacher, has         
invariably been mingled with an unpleasant sense of disapproval of          
an insidious art that knows how, in matters of moment, to move men          
like machines to a judgement that must lose all its weight with them        
upon calm reflection. Force and elegance of speech (which together          
constitute rhetoric) belong to fine art; but oratory (ars oratoria),        
being the art of playing for one's own purpose up-the weaknesses of         
men (let this purpose be ever so good in intention or even in fact)         
merits no respect whatever. Besides, both at Athens and at Rome, it         
only attained its greatest height at a time when the state was              
hastening to its decay, and genuine patriotic sentiment was a thing of      
the past. One who sees the issue clearly, and who has a command of          
language in its wealth and its purity, and who is possessed of an           
imagination that is fertile and effective in presenting his ideas, and      
whose heart, withal, turns with lively sympathy to what is truly            
good-he is the vir bonus dicendi peritus, the orator without art,           
but of great impressiveness, Cicero would have him, though he may           
not himself always always remained faithful to this ideal.                  
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 345}
-                                                                           
  After poetry, if we take charm and mental stimulation into                
account, I would give the next place to that art which comes nearer to      
it than to any other art of speech, and admits of very natural union        
with it, namely the art of tone. For though it speaks by means of mere      
sensations without concepts, and so does not, like poetry, leave            
behind it any food for reflection, still it moves the mind more             
diversely, and, although with transient, still with intenser effect.        
It is certainly, however, more a matter of enjoyment than of                
culture-the play of thought incidentally excited by it being merely         
the effect of a more or less mechanical association-and it possesses        
less worth in the eyes of reason than any other of the fine arts.           
Hence, like all enjoyment, it calls for constant change, and does           
not stand frequent repetition without inducing weariness. Its charm,        
which admits of such universal communication, appears to rest on the        
following facts. Every expression in language has an associated tone        
suited to its sense. This tone indicates, more or less, a mode in           
which the speaker is affected, and in turn evokes it in the hearer          
also, in whom conversely it then also excites the idea which in             
language is expressed with such a tone. Further, just as modulation         
is, as it were, a universal language of sensations intelligible to          
every man, so the art of tone wields the full force of this language        
wholly on its own account, namely, as a language of the affections,         
and in this way, according to the law of association, universally           
communicates the aesthetic ideas that are naturally combined                
therewith. But, further, inasmuch as those aesthetic ideas are not          
concepts or determinate thoughts, the form of the arrangement of these      
sensations (harmony and melody), taking the place of the place of           
the form of a language, only serves the purpose of giving an                
expression to the aesthetic idea of an integral whole of an                 
unutterable wealth of thought that fills the measure of a certain           
theme forming the dominant affection in the piece. This purpose is          
effectuated by means of a proposition in the accord of the                  
sensations (an accord which may be brought mathematically under             
certain rules, since it rests, in the case of tones, upon the               
numerical relation of the vibrations of the air in the same time, so        
far as there is a combination of the tones simultaneously or in             
succession). Although this mathematical form is not represented by          
means of determinate concepts, to it alone belongs the delight which        
the mere reflection upon such a number of concomitant or consecutive        
sensations couples with this their play, as the universally valid           
condition of its beauty, and it is with reference to it alone that          
taste can lay claim to a right to anticipate the judgement of every         
man.                                                                        
  But mathematics, certainly, does not play the smallest part in the        
charm and movement of the mind produced by music. Rather is it only         
the indispensable condition (conditio sine qua non) of that proportion      
of the combining as well as changing impressions which makes it             
possible to grasp them all in one and prevent them from destroying one      
another, and to let them, rather, conspire towards the production of a      
continuous movement and quickening of the mind by affections that           
are in unison with it, and thus towards a serene self-enjoyment.            
  If, on the other hand, we estimate the worth of the fine arts by the      
culture they supply to the mind, and adopt for our standard the             
expansion of the faculties whose confluence, in judgement, is               
necessary for cognition, music, then, since it plays merely with            
sensations, 'has the lowest place among the fine arts-just as it has        
perhaps the highest among those valued at the same time for their           
agreeableness. Looked at in this light, it is far excelled by the           
formative arts. For, in putting the imagination into a play which is        
at once free and adapted to the understanding, they all the while           
carry on a serious business, since they execute a product which serves      
the Concepts of understanding as a vehicle, permanent and appealing to      
us on its own account, for effectuating their union with                    
sensibility, and thus for promoting, as it were, the urbanity of the        
higher powers of cognition. The two kinds of art pursue completely          
different courses. Music advances from sensations to indefinite ideas:      
formative art from definite ideas to sensations. The latter gives a         
lasting impression, the former one that is only fleeting. The former        
sensations imagination can recall and agreeably entertain itself with,      
while the latter either vanish entirely, or else, if involuntarily          
repeated by the imagination, are more annoying to us than agreeable.        
Over and above all this, music has a certain lack of urbanity about         
it. For owing chiefly to the character of its instruments, it scatters      
its influence abroad to an uncalled-for extent (through the                 
neighbourhood), and thus, as it were, becomes obtrusive and deprives        
others, outside the musical circle, of their freedom. This is a             
thing that the arts that address themselves to the eye do not do,           
for if one is not disposed to give admittance to their impressions,         
one has only to look the other way. The case is almost on a par with        
the practice of regaling oneself with a perfume that exhales its            
odours far and wide. The man who pulls his perfumed handkerchief            
from his pocket gives a treat to all around whether they like it or         
not, and compels them, if they want to breathe at all, to be parties        
to the enjoyment, and so the habit has gone out of fashion.*                
-                                                                           
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 350}
  *Those who have recommended the singing of hymns at family prayers        
have forgotten the amount of annoyance which they give to the               
general public by such noisy (and, as a rule, for that very reason,         
pharisaical) worship, for they compel their neighbours either to            
join in the singing or else abandon their meditations.                      
-                                                                           
  Among the formative arts I would give the palm to painting: partly        
because it is the art of design and, as such, the groundwork of all         
the other formative arts; partly because it can penetrate much further      
into the region of ideas, and in conformity with them give a greater        
extension to the field of intuition than it is open to the others to        
do.                                                                         
-                                                                           
                        SS 54. Remark.                                      
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 355}
-                                                                           
  As we have often shown, an essential distinction lies between what        
pleases simply in the estimate formed of it and what gratifies              
(pleases in sensation). The latter is something which, unlike the           
former, we cannot demand from every one. Gratification (no matter           
whether its cause has its seat even in ideas) appears always to             
consist in a feeling of the furtherance of the entire life of the man,      
and hence, also of his bodily well-being, i.e., his health. And so,         
perhaps, Epicurus was not wide of the mark when he said that at bottom      
all gratification is bodily sensation, and only misunderstood               
himself in ranking intellectual and even practical delight under the        
head of gratification. Bearing in mind the latter distinction, it is        
readily explicable how even the gratification a person feels is             
capable of displeasing him (as the joy of a necessitous but                 
good-natured individual on being made the heir of an affectionate           
but penurious father), or how deep pain may still give pleasure to the      
sufferer (as the sorrow of a widow over the death of her deserving          
husband), or how there may be pleasure over and above gratification         
(as in scientific pursuits), or how a pain (as, for example, hatred,        
envy, and desire for revenge) may in addition be a source of                
displeasure. Here the delight or aversion depends upon reason, and          
is one with approbation or disapprobation. Gratification and pain,          
on the other hand, can only depend upon feeling, or upon the                
prospect of a possible well-being or the reverse (irrespective of           
source).                                                                    
  The changing free play of sensations (which do not follow any             
preconceived plan) is always a source of gratification, because it          
promotes the feeling of health; and it is immaterial whether or not we      
experience delight in the object of this play or even in the                
gratification itself when estimated in the light of reason. Also            
this gratification may amount to an affection, although we take no          
interest in the object itself, or none, at least, proportionate to the      
degree of the affection. We may divide the above play into that of          
games of chance (Gluckspiel), harmony (Tonspiel), and wit                   
(Gedankenspiel). The first stands in need of an interest, be it of          
vanity or selfseeking, but one which falls far short of that                
centered in the adopted mode of procurement. All that the second            
requires is the change of sensations, each of which has its bearing on      
affection, though without attaining to the degree of an affection, and      
excites aesthetic ideas. The third springs merely from the change of        
the representations in the judgement, which, while unproductive of any      
thought conveying an interest, yet enlivens the mind.                       
  What a fund of gratification must be afforded by play, without our        
having to fall back upon any consideration of interest, is a matter to      
which all our evening parties bear witness for without play they            
hardly ever escape falling flat. But the affections of hope, fear,          
joy, anger, and derision here engage in play, as every moment they          
change their parts and are so lively that, as by an internal motion,        
the whole vital function of the body seems to be furthered by the           
process-as is proved by a vivacity of the mind produced-although no         
one comes by anything in the way of profit or instruction. But as           
the play of chance is not one that is beautiful, we will here lay it        
aside. Music, on the contrary, and what provokes laughter are two           
kinds of play with aesthetic ideas, or even with representations of         
the understanding, by which, all said and done, nothing is thought. By      
mere force of change they yet are able to afford lively gratification.      
This furnishes pretty clear evidence that the quickening effect of          
both is physical, despite its being excited by ideas of the mind,           
and that the feeling of health, arising from a movement of the              
intestines answering to that play, makes up that entire                     
gratification of an animated gathering upon the spirit and                  
refinement of which we set such store. Not any estimate of harmony          
in tones or flashes of wit, which, with its beauty, serves only as a        
necessary vehicle, but rather the stimulated vital functions of the         
body, the affection stirring the intestines and the diaphragm, and, in      
a word, the feeling of health (of which we are only sensible upon some      
such provocation) are what constitute the gratification we                  
experience at being able to reach the body through the soul and use         
the latter as the physician of the former.                                  
  In music, the course of this play is from bodily sensation to             
aesthetic ideas (which are the objects for the affections), and then        
from these back again, but with gathered strength, to the body. In          
jest (which just as much as the former deserves to be ranked rather as      
an agreeable than a fine art) the play sets out from thoughts which         
collectively, so far as seeking sensuous expression, engage the             
activity of the body. In this presentation the understanding,               
missing what it expected, suddenly lets go its hold, with the result        
that the effect of this slackening is felt in the body by the               
oscillation of the organs. This favours the restoration of the              
equilibrium of the latter, and exerts a beneficial influence upon           
the health.                                                                 
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 360}
  Something absurd (something in which, therefore, the understanding        
can of itself find no delight) must be present in whatever is to raise      
a hearty convulsive laugh. Laughter is an all action arising from a         
strained expectation being suddenly reduced to nothing. This very           
reduction, at which certainly understanding cannot rejoice, is still        
indirectly a source of very lively enjoyment for a moment. Its cause        
must consequently lie in the influence of the representation upon           
the body and the reciprocal effect of this upon the mind. This,             
moreover, cannot depend upon the representation being objectively an        
object of gratification (for how can we derive gratification from a         
disappointment?) but must rest solely upon the fact that the reduction      
is a mere play of representations, and, as such, produces an                
equilibrium of the vital forces of the body.                                
  Suppose that some one tells the following story: An Indian at an          
Englishman's table in Surat saw a bottle of ale opened, and all the         
beer turned into froth and flowing out. The repeated exclamations of        
the Indian showed his great astonishment. "Well, what is so                 
wonderful in that?" asked the Englishman. "Oh, I'm not surprised            
myself," said the Indian, "at its getting out, but at how you ever          
managed to get it all in." At this we laugh, and it gives us hearty         
pleasure. This is not because we think ourselves, maybe, more               
quick-witted than this ignorant Indian, or because our understanding        
here brings to our notice any other ground of delight. It is rather         
that the bubble of our expectation was extended to the full and             
suddenly went off into nothing. Or, again, take the case of the heir        
of a wealthy relative being minded to make preparations for having the      
funeral obsequies on a most imposing scale, but complaining that            
things would not go right for him, because (as he said) "the more           
money I give my mourners to look sad, the more pleased they look."          
At this we laugh outright, and the reason lies in the fact that we had      
an expectation which is suddenly reduced to nothing. We must be             
careful to observe that the reduction is not one into the positive          
contrary of an expected object-for that is always something, and may        
frequently pain us-but must be a reduction to nothing. For where a          
person arouses great expectation by recounting some tale, and at the        
close its untruth becomes at once apparent to us, we are displeased at      
it. So it is, for instance, with the tale of people whose hair from         
excess of grief is said to have turned white in a single night. On the      
other hand, if a wag, wishing to cap the story, tells with the              
utmost circumstantiality of a merchant's grief, who, on his return          
journey from India to Europe with all his wealth in merchandise, was        
obliged by stress of storm to throw everything overboard, and               
grieved to such an extent that in the selfsame night his wig turned         
grey, we laugh and enjoy the tale. This is because we keep for a            
time playing on our own mistake about an object otherwise                   
indifferent to us, or rather on the idea we ourselves were following        
out, and, beating it to and fro, just as if it were a ball eluding our      
grasp, when all we intend to do is just to get it into our hands and        
hold it tight. Here our. gratification is. not excited by a knave or a      
fool getting a rebuff: for, even on its own account, the latter tale        
told with an air of seriousness would of itself be enough to set a          
whole table into roars of laughter; and the other matter would              
ordinarily not be worth a moment's thought.                                 
  It is observable that in all such cases the joke must have something      
in it capable of momentarily deceiving us. Hence, when the semblance        
vanishes into nothing, the mind looks back in order to try it over          
again, and thus by a rapidly succeeding tension and relaxation it is        
jerked to and fro and put in oscillation. As the snapping of what was,      
as it were, tightening up the string takes place suddenly (not by a         
gradual loosening), the oscillation must bring about a mental movement      
and a sympathetic internal movement of the body. This continues             
involuntarily and produces fatigue, but in so doing it also affords         
recreation (the effects of a motion conducive to health).                   
  For supposing we assume that some movement in the bodily organs is        
associated sympathetically with all our thoughts, it is readily             
intelligible how the sudden act above referred to, of shifting the          
mind now to one standpoint and now to the other, to enable it to            
contemplate its object, may involve a corresponding and reciprocal          
straining and slackening of the elastic parts of our intestines, which      
communicates itself to the diaphragm (and resembles that felt by            
ticklish people), in the course of which the lungs expel the air            
with rapidly succeeding interruptions, resulting in a movement              
conducive to health. This alone, and not what goes on in the mind,          
is the proper cause of the gratification in a thought that at bottom        
represents nothing. Voltaire said that heaven has given us two              
things to compensate us for the many miseries of life, hope and sleep.      
He might have added laughter to the list-if only the means of exciting      
it in men of intelligence were as ready to hand, and the wit or             
originality of humour which it requires were not just as rare as the        
talent is common for inventing stuff that splits the head, as mystic        
speculators do, or that breaks your neck, as the genius does, or            
that harrows the heart as sentimental novelists do (aye, and moralists      
of the same type).                                                          
  We may, therefore as I conceive, make Epicurus a present of the           
point that all gratification, even when occasioned by concepts that         
evoke aesthetic ideas, is animal, i.e., bodily sensation. For from          
this admission the spiritual feeling of respect for moral ideas, which      
is not one of gratification, but a self-esteem (an esteem for humanity      
within us) that raises us above the need of gratification, suffers not      
a whit-no nor even the less noble feeling of taste.                         
                                                   {SEC1|BK2 ^paragraph 365}
  In naivete we meet with a joint product of both the above. Naivete        
is the breaking forth of the ingenuousness originally natural to            
humanity, in opposition to the art of disguising oneself that has           
become a second nature. We laugh at the simplicity that is as yet a         
stranger to dissimulation, but we rejoice the while over the                
simplicity of nature that thwarts that art. We await the commonplace        
manner of artificial utterance, thoughtfully addressed to a fair show,      
and lo! nature stands before us in unsullied innocence-nature that          
we were quite unprepared to meet, and that he who laid it bare had          
also no intention of revealing. That the outward appearance, fair           
but false, that usually assumes such importance in our judgement, is        
here, at a stroke, turned to a nullity, that, as it were, the rogue in      
us is nakedly exposed, calls forth the movement of the mind, in two         
successive and opposite directions, agitating the body at the same          
time with wholesome motion. But that something infinitely better            
than any accepted code of manners, namely purity of mind (or at             
least a vestige of such purity), has not become wholly extinct in           
human nature, infuses seriousness and reverence into this play of           
judgement. But since it is only a manifestation that obtrudes itself        
for a moment, and the veil of a dissembling art is soon drawn over          
it again, there enters into the above feelings a touch of pity. This        
is an emotion of tenderness, playful in its way, that thus readily          
admits of combination with this sort of genial laughter. And, in fact,      
this emotion is as a rule associated with it, and, at the same time,        
is wont to make amends to the person who provides such food for our         
merriment for his embarrassment at not being wise after the manner          
of men. For that-reason art of being naif is a contradiction. But it        
is quite possible to give a representation of naivete in a                  
fictitious personage, and, rare as the art is, it is a fine art.            
With this naivete we must not confuse homely simplicity, which only         
avoids spoiling nature by artificiality, because it has no notion of        
the conventions of good society.                                            
  The humorous manner may also be ranked as a thing which in its            
enlivening influence is clearly allied to the gratification provoked        
by laughter. It belongs to originality of mind (des Geistes), though        
not to the talent for fine art. Humour, in a good sense, means the          
talent for being able to put oneself at will into a certain frame of        
mind in which everything is estimated on lines that go quite off the        
beaten track (a topsy-turvy view of things), and yet on lines that          
follow certain principles, rational in the case of such a mental            
temperament. A person with whom such variations are not a matter of         
choice is said to have humours; but if a person can assume them             
voluntarily and of set purpose (on behalf of a lively presentation          
drawn from a ludicrous contrast), he and his way of speaking are            
termed humorous. This manner belongs, however, to agreeable rather          
than to fine art, because the object of the latter must always have an      
evident intrinsic worth about it, and thus demands a certain                
seriousness in its presentation, as taste does in estimating it.            
-                                                                           
                                                                            
PART1|SEC2                                                                  
           FIRST PART CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT                       
          SECTION II. DIALECTIC OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT.                     
-                                                                           
                          SS 55.                                            
-                                                                           
  For a power of judgement to be dialectical it must first of all be        
rationalizing; that is to say, its judgements must lay claim to             
universality,* and do so a priori, for it is in the antithesis of such      
judgements that dialectic consists. Hence there is nothing dialectical      
in the irreconcilability of aesthetic judgements of sense (upon the         
agreeable and disagreeable). And in so far as each person appeals           
merely to his own private taste, even the conflict of judgements of         
taste does not form a dialectic of taste-for no one is proposing to         
make his own judgement into a universal rule. Hence the only concept        
left to us of a dialectic affecting taste is one of a dialectic of the      
critique of taste (not of taste itself) in respect of its                   
principles: for, on the question of the ground of the possibility of        
judgements of taste in general, mutually conflicting concepts               
naturally and unavoidably make their appearance. The transcendental         
critique of taste will, therefore, only include a part capable of           
bearing the name of a dialectic of the aesthetic judgement if we            
find an antinomy of the principles of this faculty which throws             
doubt upon its conformity to law, and hence also upon its inner             
possibility.                                                                
-                                                                           
                                                   {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 5}
  *Any judgement which sets up to be universal may be termed a              
rationalizing judgement (indicium ratiocinans); for so far as               
universal it may serve as the major premiss of a syllogism. On the          
other hand, only a judgement which is thought as the conclusion of a        
syllogism, and, therefore, as having an a priori foundation, can be         
called rational (indicium ratiocinatum).                                    
-                                                                           
       SS 56. Representation of the antinomy of taste.                      
-                                                                           
  The first commonplace of taste is contained in the proposition under      
cover of which every one devoid of taste thinks to shelter himself          
from reproach: every one has his own taste. This is only another way        
of saying that the determining ground of this judgement is merely           
subjective (gratification or pain), and that the judgement has no           
right to the necessary agreement of others.                                 
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 10}
  Its second commonplace, to which even those resort who concede the        
right of the judgement of taste to pronounce with validity for every        
one, is: there is no disputing about taste. This amounts to saying          
that, even though the determining ground of a judgement of taste be         
objective, it is not reducible to definite concepts, so that in             
respect of the judgement itself no decision can be reached by               
proofs, although it is quite open to us to contend upon the matter,         
and to contend with right. For though contention and dispute have this      
point in common, that they aim at bringing judgements into                  
accordance out of and by means of their mutual opposition; yet they         
differ in the latter hoping to effect this from definite concepts,          
as grounds of proof, and, consequently, adopting objective concepts as      
grounds of the judgement. But where this is considered                      
impracticable, dispute is regarded as alike out of the question.            
  Between these two commonplaces an intermediate proposition is             
readily seen to be missing. It is one which has certainly not become        
proverbial, but yet it is at the back of every one's mind. It is            
that there may be contention about taste (although not a dispute).          
This proposition, however, involves the contrary of the first one. For      
in a manner in which contention is to be allowed, there must be a:          
hope of coming to terms. Hence one must be able to reckon on grounds        
of judgement that possess more than private Validity and are thus           
not merely subjective. And yet the above principle (Every one has           
his own taste) is directly opposed to this.                                 
  The principle of taste, therefore, exhibits the following antinomy:       
  1. Thesis. The judgement of taste is not based upon concepts; for,        
if it were, it would be open to dispute (decision by means of proofs).      
  2. Antithesis. The judgement of taste is based on concepts; for           
otherwise, despite diversity of judgement, there could be no room even      
for contention in the matter (a claim to the necessary agreement of         
others with this judgement).                                                
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 15}
-                                                                           
           SS 57. Solution of the antinomy of taste.                        
-                                                                           
  There is no possibility of removing the conflict of the above             
principles, which underlie every judgement of taste (and which are          
only the two peculiarities of the judgement of taste previously set         
out in the Analytic) except by showing that the concept to which the        
object is to refer in a judgement of this kind is not taken in the          
same sense in both maxims of the aesthetic judgement; that this double      
sense, or point of view, in our estimate, is necessary for our power        
of transcendental judgement; and that nevertheless the false                
appearance arising from the confusion of one with the other is a            
natural illusion, and so unavoidable.                                       
  The judgement of taste must have reference to some concept or other,      
as otherwise it would be absolutely impossible for it to lay claim          
to necessary validity for every one. Yet it need not on that account        
be provable from a concept. For a concept may be either                     
determinable, or else at once intrinsically undetermined and                
indeterminable. A concept of the understanding, which is                    
determinable by means of predicates borrowed from sensible intuition        
and capable of corresponding to it, is of the first kind. But of the        
second kind is the transcendental rational concept of the                   
supersensible, which lies at the basis of all that sensible                 
intuition and is, therefore, incapable of being further determined          
theoretically.                                                              
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 20}
  Now the judgement of taste applies to objects of sense, but not so        
as to determine a concept of them for the understanding; for it is not      
a cognitive judgement. Hence it is a singular representation of             
intuition referable to the feeling of pleasure, and, as such, only a        
private judgement. And to that extent it would be limited in its            
validity to the individual judging: the object is for me an object          
of delight, for others it may be otherwise; every one to his taste.         
  For all that, the judgement of taste contains beyond doubt an             
enlarged reference on the part of the representation of the object          
(and at the same time on the part of the subject also), which lays the      
foundation of an extension of judgements of this kind to necessity for      
every one. This must of necessity be founded upon some concept or           
other, but such a concept as does not admit of being determined by          
intuition, and affords no knowledge of anything. Hence, too, it is a        
concept which does not afford proof of the judgement of taste. But the      
mere pure rational concept of the supersensible lying at the basis          
of the object (and of the judging subject for that matter) as object        
of sense, and thus as phenomenon, is just such a concept. For unless        
such a point of view were adopted there would be no means of saving         
the claim of the judgement of taste to universal validity. And if           
the concept forming the required basis were a concept of                    
understanding, though a mere confused one, as, let us say, of               
perfection, answering to which the sensible intuition of the beautiful      
might be adduced, then it would be at least intrinsically possible          
to found the judgement of taste upon proofs, which contradicts the          
thesis.                                                                     
  All contradiction disappears, however, if I say: The judgement of         
taste does depend upon a concept (of a general ground of the                
subjective finality of nature for the power of judgement), but one          
from which nothing can be cognized in respect of the object, and            
nothing proved, because it is in itself indeterminable and useless for      
knowledge. Yet, by means of this very concept, it acquires at the same      
time validity for every one (but with each individual, no doubt, as         
a singular judgement immediately accompanying his intuition):               
because its determining ground lies, perhaps, in the concept of what        
may be regarded as the supersensible substrate of humanity.                 
  The solution of an antinomy turns solely on the possibility of two        
apparently conflicting propositions not being in fact contradictory,        
but rather being capable of consisting together, although the               
explanation of the possibility of their concept transcends our              
faculties of cognition. That this illusion is also natural and for          
human reason unavoidable, as well as why it is so, and remains so,          
although upon the solution of the apparent contradiction it no              
longer misleads us, may be made intelligible from the above                 
considerations.                                                             
  For the concept, which the universal validity of a judgement must         
have for its basis, is taken in the same sense in both the conflicting      
judgements, yet two opposite predicates are asserted of it. The thesis      
should therefore read: The judgement of taste is not based on               
determinate concepts; but the antithesis: The judgement of taste            
does rest upon a concept, although an indeterminate one (that, namely,      
of the supersensible substrate of phenomena); and then there would          
be no conflict between them.                                                
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 25}
  Beyond removing this conflict between the claims and                      
counter-claims of taste we can do nothing. To supply a determinate          
objective principle of taste in accordance with which its judgements        
might be derived, tested, and proved, is an absolute impossibility,         
for then it would not be a judgement of taste. The subjective               
principle-that is to say, the indeterminate idea of the                     
supersensible within us -can only be indicated as the unique key to         
the riddle of this faculty, itself concealed from us in its sources;        
and there is no means of making it any more intelligible.                   
  The antinomy here exhibited and resolved rests upon the proper            
concept of taste as a merely reflective aesthetic judgement, and the        
two seemingly conflicting principles are reconciled on the ground that      
they may both be true, and this is sufficient. If, on the other             
hand, owing to the fact that the representation lying at the basis          
of the judgement of taste is singular, the determining ground of taste      
is taken, as by some it is, to be agreeableness, or, as others,             
looking to its universal validity, would have it, the principle of          
perfection, and if the definition of taste is framed accordingly,           
the result is an antinomy which is absolutely irresolvable unless we        
show the falsity of both propositions as contraries (not as simple          
contradictories). This would force the conclusion that the concept          
upon which each is founded is self-contradictory. Thus it is evident        
that the removal of the antinomy of the aesthetic judgement pursues         
a course similar to that followed by the Critique in the solution of        
the antinomies of pure theoretical reason; and that the antinomies,         
both here and in the Critique of Practical Reason, compel us,               
whether we like it or not, to look beyond the horizon of the sensible,      
and to seek in the supersensible the point of union of all our              
faculties a priori: for we are left with no other expedient to bring        
reason into harmony with itself.                                            
-                                                                           
                       REMARK 1.                                            
-                                                                           
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 30}
  We find such frequent occasion in transcendental philosophy for           
distinguishing ideas from concepts of the understanding that it may be      
of use to introduce technical terms answering to the distinction            
between them. I think that no objection will be raised to my proposing      
some. Ideas, in the most comprehensive sense of the word, are               
representations referred to an object according to a certain principle      
(subjective or objective), in so far as they can still never become         
a cognition of it. They are either referred to an intuition, in             
accordance with a merely subjective principle of the harmony of the         
cognitive faculties (imagination and understanding), and are then           
called aesthetic; or else they are referred to a concept according          
to an objective principle and yet are incapable of ever furnishing a        
cognition of the object, and are called rational ideas. In the              
latter case, the concept is a transcendent concept, and, as such,           
differs from a concept of understanding, for which an adequately            
answering experience may always be supplied, and which, on that             
account, is called immanent.                                                
  An aesthetic idea cannot become a cognition, because it is an             
intuition (of the imagination) for which an adequate concept can never      
be found. A rational idea can never become a cognition, because it          
involves a concept (of the supersensible), for which a commensurate         
intuition can never be given.                                               
  Now the aesthetic idea might, I think, be called an inexponible           
representation of the imagination, the rational idea, on the other          
hand, an indemonstrable concept of reason. The production of both is        
presupposed to be not altogether groundless, but rather (following the      
above explanation of an idea in general) to take place in obedience to      
certain principles of the cognitive faculties to which they belong          
(subjective principles in the case of the former and objective in that      
of the latter).                                                             
  Concepts of the understanding must, as such, always be                    
demonstrable (if, as in anatomy, demonstration is understood in the         
sense merely of presentation). In other words, the object answering to      
such concepts must always be capable of being given an intuition (pure      
or empirical); for only in this way can they become cognitions. The         
concept of magnitude may be given a priori in the intuition of              
space, e.g., of the right line, etc.; the concept of cause in               
impenetrability, in the impact of bodies, etc. Consequently both may        
be verified by means of an empirical intuition, i.e., the thought of        
them may be indicated (demonstrated, exhibited) in an example; and          
this it must be possible to do: for otherwise there would be no             
certainty of the thought not being empty, i.e., having no object.           
  In logic the expressions demonstrable or indemonstrable are               
ordinarily employed only in respect of propositions. A better               
designation would be to call the former propositions only mediately,        
and the latter, propositions immediately, certain. For pure                 
philosophy, too, has propositions of both these kinds-meaning               
thereby true propositions which are in the one case capable, and in         
the other incapable, of proof. But, in its character of philosophy,         
while it can, no doubt, prove on a priori grounds, it cannot                
demonstrate-unless we wish to give the complete go-by to the meaning        
of the word which makes demonstrate (ostendere, exhibere) equivalent        
to giving an accompanying presentation of the concept in intuition (be      
it in a proof or in a definition). Where the intuition is a priori          
this is called its construction, but when even the intuition is             
empirical, we have still got the illustration of the object, by             
which means objective reality is assured to the concept. Thus an            
anatomist is said to demonstrate the human eye when he renders the          
concept, of which he has previously given a discursive exposition,          
intuitable by means of the dissection of that organ.                        
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 35}
  It follows from the above that the rational concept of the                
supersensible substrate of all phenomena generally, or even of that         
which must be laid at the basis of our elective will in respect of          
moral laws, i.e., the rational concept of transcendental freedom, is        
at once specifically an indemonstrable-concept, and a rational idea,        
whereas virtue is so in a measure. For nothing can be given which in        
itself qualitatively answers in experience to the rational concept          
of the former, while in the case of virtue no empirical product of the      
above causality attains the degree that the rational idea prescribes        
as the rule.                                                                
  Just as the imagination, in the case of a rational idea, fails            
with its intuitions to attain to the given concept, so                      
understanding, in the case of an aesthetic idea, fails with its             
concepts ever to attain to the completeness of the internal                 
intuition which imagination conjoins with a given representation.           
Now since the reduction of a representation of the imagination to           
concepts is equivalent to giving its exponents, the aesthetic idea may      
be called on inexponible representation of the imagination (in its          
free play). I shall have an opportunity hereafter of dealing more           
fully with ideas of this kind. At present I confine myself to the           
remark, that both kinds of ideas, aesthetic ideas as well as rational,      
are bound to have their principles, and that the seat of these              
principles must in both cases be reason-the latter depending upon           
the objective, the former upon the subjective, principles of its            
employment.                                                                 
  Consonantly with this, GENIUS may also be defined as the faculty          
of aesthetic ideas. This serves at the same time to point out the           
reason why it is nature (the nature of the individual) and not a set        
purpose, that in products of genius gives the rule to art (as the           
production of the beautiful). For the beautiful must not be                 
estimated according to concepts, but by the final mode in which the         
imagination is attuned so as to accord with the faculty of concepts         
generally; and so rule and precept are incapable of serving as the          
requisite subjective standard for that aesthetic and unconditioned          
finality in fine art which has to make a warranted claim to being           
bound to please every one. Rather must such a standard be sought in         
the element of mere nature in the subject, which cannot be                  
comprehended under rules or concepts, that is to say, the                   
supersensible substrate of all the subject's faculties (unattainable        
by any concept of understanding), and consequently in that which forms      
the point of reference for the harmonious accord of all our                 
faculties of cognition-the production of which accord is the                
ultimate end set by the intelligible basis of our nature. Thus alone        
is it possible for a subjective and yet universally valid principle         
a priori to lie at the basis of that finality for which no objective        
principle can be prescribed.                                                
-                                                                           
                       REMARK 2.                                            
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 40}
-                                                                           
  The following important observation here naturally presents               
itself: There are three kinds of antinomies of pure reason, which,          
however, all agree in forcing reason to abandon the otherwise very          
natural assumption which takes the objects of sense for                     
things-in-themselves, and to regard them, instead, merely as                
phenomena, and to lay at their basis an intelligible substrate              
(something supersensible, the concept of which is only an idea and          
affords no proper knowledge). Apart from some such antinomy, reason         
could never bring itself to take such a step as-to adopt a principle        
so severely restricting the field of its speculation, and to submit to      
sacrifices involving the complete dissipation of so many otherwise          
brilliant hopes. For even now that it is recompensed for this loss          
by the prospect of a proportionately wider scope of action from a           
practical point of view, it is not without a pang of regret that it         
appears to part company with those hopes, and to break away from the        
old ties.                                                                   
  The reason for there being three kinds of antinomies is to be             
found in the fact that there are three faculties of cognition,              
understanding, judgement, and reason, each of which, being a higher         
faculty of cognition, must have its a priori principles. For, so far        
as reason passes judgement upon these principles themselves and             
their employment, it inexorably requires the unconditioned for the          
given conditioned in respect of them all. This can never be found           
unless the sensible, instead of being regarded as inherently                
appurtenant to things-in-themselves, is treated as a mere                   
phenomenon, and, as such, being made to rest upon something                 
supersensible (the intelligible substrate of external and internal          
nature) as the thing-in-itself. There is then (1) for the cognitive         
faculty an antinomy of reason in respect of the theoretical employment      
of understanding carried to the point of the unconditioned; (2) for         
the feeling of pleasure and displeasure an antinomy of reason in            
respect of the aesthetic employment of judgement; (3) for the               
faculty Of desire an antinomy in respect of the practical employment        
of self-legislative reason. For all these faculties have their              
fundamental a priori principles, and, following an imperative demand        
of reason, must be able to judge and to determine their object              
unconditionally in accordance with these principles.                        
  As to two of the antinomies of these higher cognitive faculties,          
those, namely, of their theoretical and of their practical employment,      
we have already shown elsewhere both that they are inevitable, if no        
cognisance is taken in such judgements of a supersensible substrate of      
the given objects as phenomena, and, on the other hand, that they           
can be solved the moment this is done. Now, as to the antinomy              
incident to the employment of judgement in conformity with the              
demand of reason, and the solution of it here given, we may say that        
to avoid facing it there are but the following alternatives. It is          
open to us to deny that any a priori principle lies at the basis of         
the aesthetic judgement of taste, with the result that all claim to         
the necessity of a universal consensus of opinion is an idle and empty      
delusion, and that a judgement of taste only deserves to be considered      
to this extent correct, that it so happens that a number share the          
same opinion, and even this, not, in truth, because an a priori             
principle is presumed to lie at the back of this agreement, but rather      
(as with the taste of the palate) because of the contingently               
resembling organization of the individuals. Or else, in the                 
alternative, we should have to suppose that the judgement of taste          
is in fact a disguised judgement of reason on the perfection                
discovered in a thing and the reference of the manifold in it to an         
end, and that it is consequently only called aesthetic on account of        
the confusion that here besets our reflection, although                     
fundamentally it is teleological. In this latter case the solution          
of the antinomy with the assistance of transcendental ideas might be        
declared otiose and nugatory, and the above laws of taste thus              
reconciled with the objects of sense, not as mere phenomena, but            
even as things-in-themselves. How unsatisfactory both of those              
alternatives alike are as a means of escape has been shown in               
several places in our exposition of judgements of taste.                    
  If, however, our deduction is at least credited with having been          
worked out on correct lines, even though it may not have been               
sufficiently clear in all its details, three ideas then stand out in        
evidence. Firstly, there is the supersensible in general, without           
further determination, as substrate of nature; secondly, this same          
supersensible as principle of the subjective finality of nature for         
our cognitive faculties; thirdly, the same supersensible again, as          
principle of the ends of freedom, and principle of the common accord        
of these ends with freedom in the moral sphere.                             
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 45}
-                                                                           
      SS 58. The idealism of the finality alike of nature                   
         and of art, as the unique principle of the                         
                  aesthetic judgement.                                      
-                                                                           
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 50}
  The principle of taste may, to begin with, be placed on either of         
two footings. For taste may be said invariably to judge on empirical        
grounds of determination and such, therefore, as are only given a           
posteriori through sense, or else it may be allowed to judge on an a        
priori ground. The former would be the empiricism of the critique of        
taste, the latter its rationalism. The first would obliterate the           
distinction that marks off the object of our delight from the               
agreeable; the second, supposing the judgement rested upon determinate      
concepts, would obliterate its distinction from the good. In this           
way beauty would have its locus standi in the world completely denied,      
and nothing but the dignity of a separate name, betokening, maybe, a        
certain blend of both the above-named kinds of delight, would be            
left in its stead. But we have shown the existence of grounds of            
delight which are a priori, and which therefore, can consist with           
the principle of rationalism, and which are yet incapable of being          
grasped by definite concepts.                                               
  As against the above, we may say that the rationalism of the              
principle of taste may take the form either of the realism of finality      
or of its idealism. Now, as a judgement of taste is not a cognitive         
judgement, and as beauty is not a property of the object considered in      
its own account, the rationalism of the principle of taste can never        
be placed in the fact that the finality in this judgement is                
regarded in thought as objective. In other words, the judgement is not      
directed theoretically, nor, therefore, logically, either (no matter        
if only in a confused estimate), to the perfection of the object,           
but only aesthetically to the harmonizing of its representation in the      
imagination with the essential principles of judgement generally in         
the subject. For this reason the judgement of taste, and the                
distinction between its realism and its idealism, can only, even on         
the principle of rationalism, depend upon its subjective finality           
interpreted in one or other of two ways. Either such subjective             
finality is, in the first case, a harmony with our judgement pursued        
as an actual (intentional) end of nature (or of art), or else, in           
the second case, it is only a supervening final harmony with the needs      
of our faculty of judgement in its relation to nature and the forms         
which nature produces in accordance with particular laws, and one that      
is independent of an end, spontaneous and contingent.                       
  The beautiful forms displayed in the organic world all plead              
eloquently on the side of the realism of the aesthetic finality of          
nature in support of the plausible assumption that beneath the              
production of the beautiful there must lie a preconceived idea in           
the producing cause-that is to say an end acting in the interest of         
our imagination. Flowers, blossoms, even the shapes of plants as a          
whole, the elegance of animal formations of all kinds, unnecessary for      
the discharge of any function on their part, but chosen as it were          
with an eye to our taste; and, beyond all else, the variety and             
harmony in the array of colours (in the pheasant, in crustacea, in          
insects, down even to the meanest flowers), so pleasing and charming        
to the eyes, but which, inasmuch as they touch the bare surf ace,           
and do not even here in any way all act the structure, of these             
creatures-a matter which might have a necessary bearing on their            
internal ends-seem to be planned entirely with a view to outward            
appearance: all these lend great weight to the mode of explanation          
which assumes actual ends of nature in favour of our aesthetic              
judgement.                                                                  
  On the other hand, not alone does reason, with its maxims                 
enjoining upon us in all cases to avoid, as far as possible, any            
unnecessary multiplication of principles, set itself against this           
assumption, but we have nature in its free formations displaying on         
all sides extensive mechanical proclivity to producing forms seemingly      
made, as it were, for the aesthetic employment of our judgement,            
without affording the least support to the supposition of a need for        
anything over and above its mechanism, as mere nature, to enable            
them to be final for our judgement apart from their being grounded          
upon any idea. The above expression, "free formations" of nature,           
is, however, here used to denote such as are originally set up in a         
fluid at rest where the volatilization or separation of some                
constituent (sometimes merely of caloric) leaves the residue on             
solidification to assume a definite shape or structure (figure or           
texture) which differs with specific differences of the matter, but         
for the same matter is invariable. Here, however, it is taken for           
granted that, as the true meaning of a fluid requires, the matter in        
the fluid is completely dissolved and not a mere admixture of solid         
particles simply held there in suspension.                                  
  The formation, then, takes place by a concursion, i.e., by a              
sudden solidification- not by a gradual transition from the fluid to        
the solid state, but, as it were, by a leap. This transition is termed      
crystallization. Freezing water offers the most familiar instance of a      
formation of this kind. There the process begins by straight threads        
of ice forming. These unite at angles of 60", whilst others                 
similarly attach themselves to them at every point until the whole has      
turned into ice. But while this is going on, the water between the          
threads of ice does not keep getting gradually more viscous, but            
remains as thoroughly fluid as it would be at a much higher                 
temperature, although it is perfectly ice-cold. The matter that             
frees itself that makes its sudden escape at the moment of                  
solidification-is a considerable quantum of caloric. As this was            
merely required to preserve fluidity, its disappearance leaves the          
existing ice not a whit colder than the water which but a moment            
before was there as fluid.                                                  
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 55}
  There are many salts and also stones of a crystalline figure which        
owe their origin in like manner to some earthly substance being             
dissolved in water under the influence of agencies little                   
understood. The drusy configurations of many minerals, of the               
cubical sulphide of lead, of the red silver ore, etc., are                  
presumably also similarly formed in water, and by the concursion of         
their particles, on their being forced by some cause or other to            
relinquish this vehicle and to unite among themselves in definite           
external shapes.                                                            
  But, further, all substances rendered fluid by heat, which have           
become solid as the result of cooling, give, when broken, internal          
evidences of a definite texture, thus suggesting the inference that         
only for the interference of their own weight or the disturbance of         
the air, the exterior would also have exhibited their proper                
specific shape. This has been observed in the case of some metals           
where the exterior of a molten mass has hardened, but the interior          
remained fluid, and then. owing to the withdrawal of the still fluid        
portion in the interior, there has been an undisturbed concursion of        
the remaining parts on the inside. A number of such mineral                 
crystallizations, such as spars, hematite, aragonite, frequently            
present extremely beautiful shapes such as it might take art all its        
time to devise; and the halo in the grotto of Antiparos is merely           
the work of water percolating through strata of gypsum.                     
  The fluid state is, to all appearance, on the whole older than the        
solid, and plants as well as animal bodies are built up out of fluid        
nutritive substance, so far as this takes form undisturbed-in the case      
of the latter, admittedly, in obedience, primarily, to a certain            
original bent of nature directed to ends (which, as will be shown in        
Part II, must not be judged aesthetically, but teleologically by the        
principle of realism); but still all the while, perhaps, also               
following the universal law of the affinity of substances in the way        
they shoot together and form in freedom. In the same way, again, where      
an atmosphere, which is a composite of different kinds of gas, is           
charged with watery fluids, and these separate from it owing to a           
reduction of the temperature, they produce snow-figures of shapes           
differing with the actual composition of the atmosphere. These are          
frequently of very artistic appearance and of extreme beauty. So            
without at all derogating from the teleological principle by which          
an organization is judged, it is readily conceivable how with beauty        
of flowers, of the plumage of birds, of crustacea, both as to their         
shape and their colour, we have only what may be ascribed to nature         
and its capacity for originating in free activity aesthetically             
final forms, independently of any particular guiding ends, according        
to chemical laws, by means of the chemical integration of the               
substance requisite for the organization.                                   
  But what shows plainly that the principle of the ideality of the          
finality in the beauty of nature is the one upon which we ourselves         
invariably take our stand in our aesthetic judgements, forbidding us        
to have recourse to any realism of a natural end in favour of our           
faculty of representation as a principle of explanation, is that in         
our general estimate of beauty we seek its standard a priori in             
ourselves, and, that the aesthetic faculty is itself legislative in         
respect of the judgement whether anything is beautiful or not. This         
could not be so on the assumption of a realism of the finality of           
nature; because in that case we should have to go to nature for             
instruction as to what we should deem beautiful, and the judgement          
of taste would be subject to empirical principles. For in such an           
estimate the question does not turn on what nature is, or even on what      
it is for us in the way of an end, but on how we receive it. For            
nature to have fashioned its forms for our delight would inevitably         
imply an objective finality on the part of nature, instead of a             
subjective finality resting on the play of imagination in its freedom,      
where it is we who receive nature with favour, and not nature that          
does us a favour. That nature affords us an opportunity for perceiving      
the inner finality in the relation of our mental powers engaged in the      
estimate of certain of its products, and, indeed, such a finality as        
arising from a supersensible basis is to be pronounced necessary and        
of universal validity, is a property of nature which cannot belong          
to it as its end, or rather, cannot be estimated by us to be such an        
end. For otherwise the judgement that would be determined by reference      
to such an end would found upon heteronomy, instead of founding upon        
autonomy and being free, as befits a judgement of taste.                    
  The principle of the idealism of finality is still more clearly           
apparent in fine art. For the point that sensations do not enable us        
to adopt an aesthetic realism of finality (which would make art merely      
agreeable instead of beautiful) is one which it enjoys in common            
with beautiful nature. But the further point that the delight               
arising from aesthetic ideas must not be made dependent upon the            
successful attainment of determinate ends (as an art mechanically           
directed to results), and that, consequently, even in the case of           
the rationalism of the principle, an ideality of the ends and not           
their reality is fundamental, is brought home to us by the fact that        
fine art, as such, must not be regarded as a product of                     
understanding and science, but of genius, and must, therefore,              
derive its rule from aesthetic ideas, which are essentially                 
different from rational ideas of determinate ends.                          
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 60}
  Just as the ideality of objects of sense as phenomena is the only         
way of explaining the possibility of their forms admitting of a priori      
determination, so, also, the idealism of the finality in estimating         
the beautiful in nature and in art is the only hypothesis upon which a      
critique can explain the possibility of a judgement of taste that           
demands a priori validity for every one (yet without basing the             
finality represented in the object upon concepts).                          
-                                                                           
           SS 59. Beauty as the symbol of morality.                         
-                                                                           
 Intuitions are always required to verify the reality of our concepts.      
If the concepts are empirical, the intuitions are called examples:          
if they are pure concepts of the understanding, the intuitions go by        
the name of schemata. But to call for a verification of the                 
objective reality of rational concepts, i.e., of ideas, and, what is        
more, on behalf of the theoretical cognition of such a reality, is          
to demand an impossibility, because absolutely no intuition adequate        
to them can be given.                                                       
  All hypotyposis (presentation, subjectio sub adspectum) as a              
rendering in terms of sense, is twofold. Either it is schematic, as         
where the intuition corresponding to a concept comprehended by the          
understanding is given a priori, or else it is symbolic, as where           
the concept is one which only reason can think, and to which no             
sensible intuition can be adequate. In the latter case the concept          
is supplied with an intuition such that the procedure of judgement          
in dealing with it is merely analogous to that which it observes in         
schematism. In other words, what agrees with the concept is merely the      
rule of this procedure, and not the intuition itself. Hence the             
agreement is merely in the form of reflection, and not in the content.      
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 65}
  Notwithstanding the adoption of the word symbolic by modern               
logicians in a sense opposed to an intuitive mode of representation,        
it is a wrong use of the word and subversive of its true meaning;           
for the symbolic is only a mode of any intrinsic connection with the        
intuition of sentation is, in fact, divisible into the schematic            
and the symbolic. Both are hypotyposes, i.e., presentations                 
(exhibitiones), not mere marks. Marks are merely designations of            
concepts by the aid of accompanying sensible signs devoid of any            
intrinsic connection with the intuition of the object. Their sole           
function is to afford a means of reinvoking the concepts according          
to the imagination's law of association-a purely subjective role. Such      
marks are either words or visible (algebraic or even mimetic) signs,        
simply as expressions for concepts.*                                        
-                                                                           
  *The intuitive mode of knowledge must be contrasted with the              
discursive mode (not with the symbolic). The former is either               
schematic, by mean demonstration, symbolic, as a representation             
following a mere analogy.                                                   
-                                                                           
  All intuitions by which a priori concepts are given a foothold            
are, therefore, either schemata or symbols. Schemata contain direct,        
symbols indirect, presentations of the concept. Schemata effect this        
presentation demonstratively, symbols by the aid of an analogy (for         
which recourse is had even to empirical intuitions), in which               
analogy judgement performs a double function: first in applying the         
concept to the object of a sensible intuition, and then, secondly,          
in applying the mere rule of its reflection upon that intuition to          
quite another object, of which the former is but the symbol. In this        
way, a monarchical state is represented as a living body when it is         
governed by constitutional laws, but as a mere machine (like a              
handmill) when it is governed by an individual absolute will; but in        
both cases the representation is merely symbolic. For there is              
certainly no likeness between a despotic state and a handmill, whereas      
there surely is between the rules of reflection upon both and their         
causality. Hitherto this function has been but little analysed, worthy      
as it is of a deeper study. Still this is not the place to dwell            
upon it. In language we have many such indirect presentations modelled      
upon an analogy enabling the expression in question to contain, not         
the proper schema for the concept, but merely a symbol for reflection.      
Thus the words ground (support, basis), to depend (to be held up            
from above), to flow from (instead of to follow), substance (as             
Locke puts it: the support of accidents), and numberless others, are        
not schematic, but rather symbolic hypotyposes, and express concepts        
without employing a direct intuition for the purpose, but only drawing      
upon an analogy with one, i.e., transferring the reflection upon an         
object of intuition to quite a new concept, and one with which perhaps      
no intuition could ever directly correspond. Supposing the name of          
knowledge may be given to what only amounts to a mere mode of               
representation (which is quite permissible where this is not a              
principle of the theoretical determination of the object in respect of      
what it is in itself, but of the practical determination of what the        
idea of it ought to be for us and for its final employment), then           
all our knowledge of God is merely symbolic; and one who takes it,          
with the properties of understanding, will, and so forth, which only        
evidence their objective reality in beings of this world, to be             
schematic, falls into anthropomorphism, just as, if he abandons             
every intuitive element, he falls into Deism which furnishes no             
knowledge whatsoever-not even from a practical point of view.               
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 70}
  Now, I say, the beautiful is the symbol of the morally good, and          
only in this light (a point of view natural to every one, and one           
which every one exacts from others as a duty) does it give us pleasure      
with an attendant claim to the agreement of every one else,                 
whereupon the mind becomes conscious of a certain ennoblement and           
elevation above mere sensibility to pleasure from impressions of            
sense, and also appraises the worth of others on the score of a like        
maxim of their judgement. This is that intelligible to which taste, as      
noticed in the preceding paragraph, extends its view. It is, that is        
to say, what brings even our higher cognitive faculties into common         
accord, and is that apart from which sheer contradiction would arise        
between their nature and the claims put forward by taste. In this           
faculty, judgement does not find itself subjected to a heteronomy of        
laws of experience as it does in the empirical estimate of things-in        
respect of the objects of such a pure delight it gives the law to           
itself, just as reason does in respect of the faculty of desire. Here,      
too, both on account of this inner possibility in the subject, and          
on account of the external possibility of a nature harmonizing              
therewith, it finds a reference in itself to something in the               
subject itself and outside it, and which is not nature, nor yet             
freedom, but still is connected with the ground of the latter, i.e.,        
the supersensible-a something in which the theoretical faculty gets         
bound up into unity with the practical in an intimate and obscure           
manner. We shall bring out a few points of this analogy, while              
taking care, at the same time, not to let the points of difference          
escape us.                                                                  
  (1) The beautiful pleases immediately (but only in reflective             
intuition, not, like morality, in its concept). (2) It pleases apart        
from all interest (pleasure in the morally good is no doubt                 
necessarily bound up with an interest, but not with one of the kind         
that are antecedent to the judgement upon the delight, but with one         
that judgement itself for the first time calls into existence). (3)         
The freedom of the imagination (consequently of our faculty in respect      
of its sensibility) is, in estimating the beautiful, represented as in      
accord with the understanding's conformity to law (in moral judgements      
the freedom of the will is thought as the harmony of the latter with        
itself according to universal laws of Reason). (4) The subjective           
principles of the estimate of the beautiful is represented as               
universal, i.e., valid for every man, but as incognizable by means          
of any universal concept (the objective principle of morality is set        
forth as also universal, i.e., for all individuals, and, at the same        
time, for all actions of the same individual, and, besides, as              
cognizable by means of a universal concept). For this reason the moral      
judgement not alone admits of definite constitutive principles, but is      
only possible by adopting these principles and their universality as        
the ground of its maxims.                                                   
  Even common understanding is wont to pay regard to this analogy; and      
we frequently apply to beautiful objects of nature or of art names          
that seem to rely upon the basis of a moral estimate. We call               
buildings or trees majestic and stately, or plains laughing and gay;        
even colours are called innocent, modest, soft, because they excite         
sensations containing something analogous to the consciousness of           
the state of mind produced by moral judgements. Taste makes, as it          
were, the transition from the charm of sense to habitual moral              
interest possible without too violent a leap, for it represents the         
imagination, even in its freedom, as amenable to a final determination      
for understanding, and teaches us to find, even in sensuous objects, a      
free delight apart from any charm of sense.                                 
-                                                                           
          SS 60. APPENDIX. The methodology of taste.                        
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 75}
-                                                                           
  The division of a critique into elementology and methodology-a            
division which is introductory to science-is one inapplicable to the        
critique of taste. For there neither is, nor can be, a science of           
the beautiful, and the judgement of taste is not determinable by            
principles. For, as to the element of science in every art -a matter        
which turns upon truth in the presentation of the object of the             
art-while this is, no doubt, the indispensable condition (conditio          
sine qua non) of fine art, it is not itself fine art. Fine art,             
therefore, has only got a manner (modus), and not a method of teaching      
(methodus). The master must illustrate what the pupil is to achieve         
and how achievement is to be attained, and the proper function of           
the universal rules to which he ultimately reduces his treatment is         
rather that of supplying a convenient text for recalling its chief          
moments to the pupil's mind, than of prescribing them to him. Yet,          
in all this, due regard must be paid to a certain ideal which art must      
keep in view, even though complete success ever eludes its happiest         
efforts. Only by exciting the pupil's imagination to conformity with a      
given concept, by pointing out how the expression falls short of the        
idea to which, as aesthetic, the concept itself fails to attain, and        
by means of severe criticism, is it possible to prevent his promptly        
looking upon the examples set before him as the prototypes of               
excellence, and as models for him to imitate, without submission to         
any higher standard or to his own critical judgement. This would            
result in genius being stifled, and, with it, also the freedom of           
the imagination in its very conformity to law-a freedom without             
which a fine art is not possible, nor even as much as a correct             
taste of one's own for estimating it.                                       
  The propaedeutic to all fine art, so far as the highest degree of         
its perfection is what is in view, appears to lie, not in precepts,         
but in the culture of the mental powers produced by a sound                 
preparatory education in what are called the humaniora-so called,           
presumably, because humanity signifies, on the one hand, the universal      
feeling of sympathy, and, on the other, the faculty of being able to        
communicate universally one's inmost self-properties constituting in        
conjunction the befitting social spirit of mankind, in                      
contradistinction to the narrow life of the lower animals. There was        
an age and there were nations in which the active impulse towards a         
social life regulated by laws-what converts a people into a                 
permanent community-grappled with the huge difficulties presented by        
the trying problem of bringing freedom (and therefore equality also)        
into union with constraining force (more that of respect and dutiful        
submission than of fear). And such must have been the age, and such         
the nation, that first discovered the art of reciprocal                     
communication of ideas between the more cultured and ruder sections of      
the community, and how to bridge the difference between the                 
amplitude and refinement of the former and the natural simplicity           
and originality of the latter-in this way hitting upon that mean            
between higher culture and the modest worth of nature, that forms           
for taste also, as a sense common to all mankind, that true standard        
which no universal rules can supply.                                        
  Hardly will a later age dispense with those models. For nature            
will ever recede farther into the background, so that eventually, with      
no permanent example retained from the past, a future age would scarce      
be in a position to form a concept of the happy union, in one and           
the same people, of the law-directed constraint belonging to the            
highest culture, with the force and truth of a free nature sensible of      
its proper worth.                                                           
  However, taste is, in the ultimate analysis, a critical faculty that      
judges of the rendering of moral ideas in terms of sense (through           
the intervention of a certain analogy in our reflection on both);           
and it is this rendering also, and the increased sensibility,               
founded upon it, for the feeling which these ideas evoke (termed moral      
sense), that are the origin of that pleasure which taste declares           
valid for mankind in general and not merely for the private feeling of      
each individual. This makes it clear that the true propaedeutic for         
laying the foundations of taste is the development of moral ideas           
and the culture of the moral feeling. For only when sensibility is          
brought into harmony with moral feeling can genuine taste assume a          
definite unchangeable form.                                                 
                                                  {PART1|SEC2 ^paragraph 80}
-                                                                           
                                                                            
                                                                            

Electronically Enhanced Text  (C) Copyright 1991, 1992, World Library, Inc. 
--------------------------------------------------------------